November 02, 2010 <Back to Index>
PAGE SPONSOR |
George Boole (2 November 1815 – 8 December 1864) was an English mathematician and philosopher. As the inventor of Boolean logic — the basis of modern digital computer logic — Boole is regarded in hindsight as a founder of the field of computer science. Boole said,
George Boole's father, John Boole (1779 – 1848), was a tradesman of limited means, but of "studious character and active mind". Being especially interested in mathematical science and logic,
the father gave his son his first lessons; but the extraordinary
mathematical talents of George Boole did not manifest themselves in
early life. At first, his favorite subject was classics. He was very weak when he was born. It was not until his successful establishment of a school at Lincoln, its removal to Waddington, and later his appointment in 1849 as the first professor of mathematics of then Queen's College, Cork in Ireland (now University College Cork, where the library, underground lecture theatre complex and the Boole Centre for Research in Informatics are named in his honour) that his mathematical skills were fully realized. In 1855 he married Mary Everest (niece of George Everest), who later, as Mrs. Boole, wrote several useful educational works on her husband's principles. To
the broader public Boole was known only as the author of numerous
abstruse papers on mathematical topics, and of three or four distinct
publications that have become standard works. His earliest published
paper was the "Researches in the theory of analytical transformations,
with a special application to the reduction of the general equation of
the second order." printed in the Cambridge Mathematical Journal in February 1840 (Volume 2, no. 8, pp. 64–73), and it led to a friendship between Boole and D.F. Gregory,
the editor of the journal, which lasted until the premature death of
the latter in 1844. A long list of Boole's memoirs and detached papers,
both on logical and mathematical topics, are found in the Catalogue of Scientific Memoirs published by the Royal Society, and in the supplementary volume on Differential Equations, edited by Isaac Todhunter. To the Cambridge Mathematical Journal and its successor, the Cambridge and Dublin Mathematical Journal, Boole contributed twenty-two articles in all. In the third and fourth series of the Philosophical Magazine are found sixteen papers. The Royal Society printed six important memoirs in the Philosophical Transactions, and a few other memoirs are to be found in the Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh and of the Royal Irish Academy, in the Bulletin de l'Académie de St-Pétersbourg for 1862 (under the name G Boldt, vol. iv. pp. 198–215), and in Crelle's Journal. Also included is a paper on the mathematical basis of logic, published in the Mechanic's Magazine in 1848. The works of Boole are thus contained in about fifty scattered articles and a few separate publications. Only two systematic treatises on mathematical subjects were completed by Boole during his lifetime. The well-known Treatise on Differential Equations appeared in 1859, and was followed, the next year, by a Treatise on the Calculus of Finite Differences,
designed to serve as a sequel to the former work. These treatises are
valuable contributions to the important branches of mathematics in
question. To a certain extent these works embody the more important
discoveries of their author. In the sixteenth and seventeenth chapters
of the Differential Equations we
find, for instance, an account of the general symbolic method, the bold
and skilful employment of which led to Boole's chief discoveries, and
of a general method in analysis, originally described in his famous memoir printed in the Philosophical Transactions for
1844. Boole was one of the most eminent of those who perceived that the
symbols of operation could be separated from those of quantity and
treated as distinct objects of calculation. His principal characteristic was perfect confidence in any result obtained by the
treatment of symbols in accordance with their primary laws and
conditions, and an almost unrivalled skill and power in tracing out
these results. During
the last few years of his life Boole was constantly engaged in
extending his researches with the object of producing a second edition
of his Differential Equations much more complete than the first edition, and part of his last vacation was spent in the libraries of the Royal Society and the British Museum;
but this new edition was never completed. Even the manuscripts left at
his death were so incomplete that Todhunter, into whose hands they were
put, found it impossible to use them in the publication of a second
edition of the original treatise, and printed them, in 1865, in a
supplementary volume. With the exception of Augustus De Morgan, Boole was probably the first English mathematician since the time of John Wallis who had also written upon logic.
His novel views of logical method were due to the same profound
confidence in symbolic reasoning to which he had successfully trusted
in mathematical investigation. Speculations concerning a calculus of reasoning had at different times occupied Boole's thoughts, but it was not till the
spring of 1847 that he put his ideas into the pamphlet called Mathematical Analysis of Logic.
Boole afterwards regarded this as a hasty and imperfect exposition of
his logical system, and he desired that his much larger work, An Investigation of the Laws of Thought (1854), on Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities,
should alone be considered as containing a mature statement of his
views. This ushered in a new focus on the nature of evidence, argument,
and proof. Nevertheless, there is a charm of originality about his
earlier logical work that is easy to appreciate.
He
did not regard logic as a branch of mathematics, as the title of his
earlier pamphlet might be taken to imply, but he pointed out such a deep analogy between the symbols of algebra and those that can be made, in his opinion, to represent logical forms and syllogisms,
that we can hardly help saying that (especially his) formal logic is
mathematics restricted to the two quantities, 0 and 1. By unity Boole
denoted the universe of thinkable objects; literal symbols, such as x, y, z, v, u, etc., were used with the elective meaning attaching to common adjectives and substantives. Thus, if x = horned and y = sheep, then the successive acts of election represented by x and y,
if performed on unity, give the whole of the class horned sheep. Boole
showed that elective symbols of this kind obey the same primary laws of combination as
algebraic symbols, whence it followed that they could be added,
subtracted, multiplied and even divided, almost exactly in the same
manner as numbers. Thus, (1 – x)
would represent the operation of selecting all things in the world
except horned things, that is, all not horned things, and (1 – x) (1 – y) would give us all things neither horned nor sheep. By the use of such symbols propositions could be reduced to the form of equations, and the syllogistic conclusion from two premises was obtained by eliminating the middle term according to ordinary algebraic rules. Still more original and remarkable, however, was that part of his system, fully stated in his Laws of Thought, formed a general symbolic method of logical inference.
Given any propositions involving any number of terms, Boole showed how,
by the purely symbolic treatment of the premises, to draw any
conclusion logically contained in those premises. The second part of the Laws of Thought contained
a corresponding attempt to discover a general method in probabilities,
which should enable us from the given probabilities of any system of
events to determine the consequent probability of any other event
logically connected with the given events. In 1921 the economist John Maynard Keynes published
a book that has become a classic on probability theory, "A Treatise of
Probability." Keynes's comments about Boole's theory of probability
were generally taken to be the definitive statement on the subject.
Keynes believed that Boole had made a fundamental error that vitiated
much of his analysis. In a recent book, "The Last Challenge Problem,"
David Miller provides a general method in accord with Boole's system,
and attempts to solve the problems recognized earlier by Keynes and
others. Though
Boole published little except his mathematical and logical works, his
acquaintance with general literature was wide and deep. Dante was his favourite poet, and he preferred the Paradiso to the Inferno. The metaphysics of Aristotle, the ethics of Spinoza, the philosophical works of Cicero,
and many kindred works, were also frequent subjects of study. His
reflections upon scientific, philosophical and religious questions are
contained in four addresses upon The Genius of Sir Isaac Newton, The Right Use of Leisure, The Claims of Science and The Social Aspect of Intellectual Culture, which he delivered and printed at different times. The
personal character of Boole inspired all his friends with the deepest
esteem. He was marked by true modesty, and his life was given to the
single-minded pursuit of truth. Though he received a medal from the Royal Society for his memoir of 1844, and the honorary degree of LL.D. from the University of Dublin,
he neither sought nor received the ordinary rewards to which his
discoveries would entitle him. On 8 December 1864, in the full vigour
of his intellectual powers, he died of an attack of fever, ending in effusion on the lungs.
He is buried in the Church of Ireland cemetery of St Michael's, Church
Road, Blackrock (a suburb of Cork City). There is a commemorative
plaque inside the adjoining church. |