April 05, 2011 <Back to Index>
PAGE SPONSOR |
Thomas Hobbes (5 April 1588 – 4 December 1679), in some older texts Thomas Hobbs of Malmsbury, was an English philosopher, remembered today for his work on political philosophy. His 1651 book Leviathan established the foundation for most of Western political philosophy from the perspective of social contract theory. Hobbes
was a champion of absolutism for the sovereign but he also developed
some of the fundamentals of European liberal thought: the right of the
individual; the natural equality of all men; the artificial character
of the political order (which led to the later distinction between civil
society and the
state); the view that all legitimate political power must be
"representative" and based on the consent of the people; and a liberal
interpretation of law which leaves people free to do whatever the law
does not explicitly forbid. Hobbes
also contributed to a diverse array of fields, including history, geometry,
physics
of gases, theology, ethics,
general philosophy,
and political
science. His account of human nature as self-interested cooperation
has proved to be an enduring theory in the field of philosophical
anthropology. He was one of the main philosophers who founded materialism. Thomas
Hobbes was born in Wiltshire, England on 5 April 1588, some
sources say at Malmesbury.
Born
prematurely when his mother heard of the coming invasion of the Spanish
Armada, Hobbes later reported that "my mother gave birth to twins:
myself and fear." His childhood is almost a
complete blank, and his mother's name is unknown. His father, also named
Thomas, was the vicar of Charlton and Westport.
Thomas
Sr. abandoned his three children to the care of an older
brother, Thomas junior's uncle Francis, when he was forced to flee to
London after being involved in a fight with a clergyman outside his own
church. Hobbes was educated at Westport church from the age of four,
passed to the Malmesbury
school and then to
a private school kept by a young man named Robert Latimer, a graduate
of the University
of
Oxford. Hobbes was a good pupil, and around 1603 he went up to
Magdalen Hall, which is most closely related to Hertford
College,
Oxford. The principal John
Wilkinson was a Puritan,
and
he had some influence on Hobbes. At
university, Hobbes appears to have followed his own curriculum; he was
"little attracted by the scholastic learning". He did not complete his B.A. degree until 1608, but he
was recommended by Sir James Hussey, his master at Magdalen, as tutor
to William, the son of William
Cavendish, Baron of Hardwick (and later Earl
of
Devonshire), and began a life-long connection with that family. Hobbes
became a companion to the younger William and they both took part in a grand
tour in 1610.
Hobbes was exposed to European scientific and critical methods during
the tour in contrast to the scholastic
philosophy which he
had learned in Oxford. His scholarly efforts at the time were aimed at
a careful study of classic Greek and Latin authors, the outcome of
which was, in 1628, his great translation of Thucydides' History
of
the Peloponnesian War, the first translation of that work
into English from a Greek manuscript. Although
he associated with literary figures like Ben
Jonson and thinkers
such as Francis
Bacon, he did not extend his efforts into philosophy until after
1629. His employer Cavendish, then the Earl of Devonshire, died of the plague in
June 1628. The widowed
countess dismissed Hobbes but he soon found work, again as a tutor,
this time to the son of Sir Gervase Clifton. This task, chiefly spent
in Paris, ended in 1631 when he again found work with the Cavendish
family, tutoring the son of his previous pupil. Over the next seven
years as well as tutoring he expanded his own knowledge of philosophy,
awakening in him curiosity over key philosophic debates. He visited Florence in 1636 and later was a
regular debater in philosophic groups in Paris, held together by Marin
Mersenne. From 1637 he considered himself a philosopher and scholar. Hobbes's
first area of study was an interest in the physical doctrine of motion
and physical momentum. Despite his interest in this phenomenon, he
disdained experimental work as in physics.
He
went on to conceive the system of thought to the elaboration of
which he would devote his life. His scheme was first to work out, in a
separate treatise, a systematic doctrine of body, showing how physical
phenomena were universally explicable in terms of motion, at least as
motion or mechanical action was then understood. He then singled out
Man from the realm of Nature and plants. Then, in another treatise, he
showed what specific bodily motions were involved in the production of
the peculiar phenomena of sensation, knowledge, affections and passions
whereby Man came into relation with Man. Finally he considered, in his
crowning treatise, how Men were moved to enter into society, and argued
how this must be regulated if Men were not to fall back into
"brutishness and misery". Thus he proposed to unite the separate
phenomena of Body, Man, and the State. Hobbes
came home, in 1637, to a country riven with discontent which disrupted
him from the orderly execution of his philosophic plan. However, by the
end of the Short
Parliament in 1640,
he had written a short treatise called The Elements of Law,
Natural and Politic. It was not published and only circulated among
his acquaintances in manuscript form. A pirated version, however, was
published about ten years later. Although it seems that much of The Elements of Law was composed before the
sitting of the Short
Parliament, there are polemical pieces of the work that clearly
mark the influences of the rising political crisis. Nevertheless, many
(though not all) elements of Hobbes's political thought were unchanged
between The Elements
of Law and Leviathan, which demonstrates that the
events of the English
Civil
War had
little effect on his contractarian methodology. It should be noted,
however, that the arguments in Leviathan were modified fromThe
Elements of Law when
it
came to the necessity of consent in creating political obligation.
Namely, Hobbes wrote in The
Elements
of Law that
Patrimonial kingdoms were not necessarily formed by the consent of the
governed, while in Leviathan he argued that they were.
This was perhaps a reflection either of Hobbes's thoughts concerning the engagement
controversy or of
his reaction to treatises published by Patriarchalists,
such
as Sir
Robert
Filmer, between 1640 and 1651. When in
November 1640 the Long
Parliament succeeded
the
Short, Hobbes felt he was a marked man by the circulation of his
treatise and fled to Paris. He did not return for eleven years. In
Paris he rejoined the coterie about Mersenne, and wrote a critique of
the Meditations on
First Philosophy of Descartes,
which
was printed as third among the sets of "Objections" appended,
with "Replies" from Descartes in 1641. A different set of remarks on
other works by Descartes succeeded only in ending all correspondence
between the two. Hobbes
also extended his own works somewhat, working on the third section, De
Cive, which was finished in November 1641. Although it was
initially only circulated privately, it was well received, and included
lines of argumentation to be repeated a decade later in the Leviathan.
He
then returned to hard work on the first two sections of his work and
published little except for a short treatise on optics (Tractatus
opticus) included in the collection of scientific tracts published
by Mersenne as Cogitata
physico-mathematica in
1644. He built a good reputation in philosophic circles and in 1645 was
chosen with Descartes, Gilles
de
Roberval and
others, to referee the controversy between John
Pell and Longomontanus over the problem of squaring
the
circle. The English
Civil
War broke out
in 1642, and when the Royalist cause began to decline in
the middle of 1644 there was an exodus of the king's supporters to
Europe. Many came to Paris and were known to Hobbes. This revitalised
Hobbes's political interests and the De Cive was republished and more widely distributed. The printing began
in 1646 by Samuel
de
Sorbiere through
the Elsevier
press at Amsterdam with
a
new preface and some new notes in reply to objections. In 1647,
Hobbes was engaged as mathematical instructor to the young Charles,
Prince
of Wales, who had come over from Jersey around July.
This engagement lasted until 1648 when Charles went to Holland. The
company of the exiled royalists led Hobbes to produce an English book
to set forth his theory of civil government in relation to the
political crisis resulting from the war. The State, it now seemed to
Hobbes, might be regarded as a great artificial man or monster (Leviathan), composed
of men, with a life that might be traced from its generation
under pressure of human needs to its dissolution through civil strife
proceeding from human passions. The work was closed with a general
"Review and Conclusion", in direct response to the war which raised the
question of the subject's right to change allegiance when a former
sovereign's power to protect was irrecoverably gone. Also he criticized
religious doctrines on rationalistic grounds in the Commonwealth. During
the years of the composition of Leviathan he remained in or near
Paris. In 1647 Hobbes was overtaken by a serious illness which disabled
him for six months. On recovering from this near fatal disorder, he
resumed his literary task, and carried it steadily forward to
completion by the year 1650. Meanwhile, a translation of De Cive was being produced; there
has been much scholarly disagreement over whether Hobbes translated the
work himself or not. In 1650,
a pirated edition of The
Elements
of Law, Natural and Politic was
published. It was
divided into two separate small volumes (Human Nature, or the
Fundamental Elements of Policie and De corpore politico, or
the Elements of Law, Moral and Politick). In 1651 the translation of De
Cive was
published under the title of Philosophicall
Rudiments
concerning Government and Society. Meanwhile, the printing of the greater work was proceeding, and finally it appeared
about the middle of 1651, under the title of Leviathan,
or
the Matter, Forme, and Power of a Common Wealth, Ecclesiasticall and
Civil, with a famous title-page engraving in which, from behind
hills overlooking a landscape, there towered the body (above the waist)
of a crowned giant, made up of tiny figures of human beings and bearing sword and crozier in the two hands. The work
had immediate impact. Soon Hobbes was more lauded and decried than any
other thinker of his time. However, the first effect of its publication
was to sever his link with the exiled royalists, forcing him to appeal
to the revolutionary English government for protection. The exiles
might very well have killed him; the secularist spirit of his book
greatly angered both Anglicans and French Catholics. Hobbes fled back
home, arriving in London in the winter of 1651. Following his
submission to the council of state he was allowed to subside into
private life in Fetter
Lane. In Leviathan,
Hobbes
set out his doctrine of the foundation of states and legitimate governments - based on social
contract
theories. Leviathan was written during the English
Civil
War; much of the book is occupied with demonstrating the
necessity of a strong central authority to avoid the evil of discord
and civil war. Beginning
from a mechanistic understanding of human
beings and the passions, Hobbes postulates what life would be like
without government, a condition which he calls the state
of
nature. In that state, each person would have a right, or
license, to everything in the world. This, Hobbes argues, would lead to
a "war of all against all" (bellum
omnium
contra omnes), and thus lives that are "solitary, poor,
nasty, brutish, and short". To escape
this state of war, men in the state of nature accede to a social
contract and
establish a civil
society. According to Hobbes, society is a population beneath a sovereign authority,
to whom all individuals in that society cede their natural rights for
the sake of protection. Any abuses of power by this authority are to be
accepted as the price of peace. However, he also states that in severe
cases of abuse, rebellion is expected. In particular, the doctrine of separation
of
powers is
rejected: the sovereign must control
civil, military, judicial and ecclesiastical powers. Leviathan was also well-known for its
radical religious views, which were often Hobbes's attempt to
reinterpret scripture from his materialist assumptions. His denial of
incorporeal entities led him to write, for example, that Heaven and Hell were places on Earth, and to take other positions out of sync with church teachings of his time.
Much has been made of his religious views by scholars such as Richard
Tuck and J.G.A. Pocock, but there is still widespread disagreement about the
significance of Leviathan's
contents
concerning religion. Many have taken the work to mean that
Hobbes was an atheist, while others find the evidence for this position
insufficient.
Hobbes
now
turned to complete the fundamental treatise of his philosophical
system. He worked so steadily that De
Corpore was first
printed in 1654. Also in 1654, a small treatise, Of Liberty and Necessity,
was
published by Bishop John
Bramhall, addressed at Hobbes. Bramhall, a strong Arminian,
had
met and debated with Hobbes and afterwards wrote down his views and
sent them privately to be answered in this form by Hobbes. Hobbes duly
replied, but not for publication. But a French acquaintance took a copy
of the reply and published it with "an extravagantly laudatory
epistle." Bramhall countered in 1655, when he printed everything that
had passed between them (under the title of A Defence of the True
Liberty of Human Actions from Antecedent or Extrinsic Necessity).
In 1656 Hobbes was ready with The
Questions
concerning Liberty, Necessity and Chance, in which he
replied "with astonishing force" to the bishop. As perhaps the first
clear exposition of the psychological doctrine of determinism, Hobbes's
own two pieces were important in the history of the free-will controversy. The bishop
returned to the charge in 1658 with Castigations
of
Mr Hobbes's Animadversions, and also included a bulky appendix
entitled The
Catching of Leviathan the Great Whale. Hobbes never took any notice
of the Castigations.
Beyond
the
spat with Bramhall, Hobbes was caught in a series of conflicts from
the time of publishing his De
Corpore in
1655. In Leviathan he
had
assailed the system of the original universities. Because Hobbes
was so evidently opposed to the existing academic arrangements, and
because De Corpore contained not only
tendentious views on mathematics, but an unacceptable proof of the squaring of
the circle (which
was apparently an afterthought), mathematicians took him to be a target
for polemics. John
Wallis was not the
first such opponent, but he tenaciously pursued Hobbes. The resulting
controversy continued well into the 1670s. Hobbes
published, in 1658, the final section of his philosophical system,
completing the scheme he had planned more than twenty years before. De
Homine consisted
for
the most part of an elaborate theory of vision. The remainder of
the treatise dealt cursorily with some of the topics more fully treated
in the Human Nature and the Leviathan. In
addition to publishing some controversial writings on mathematics and
physics, Hobbes also continued to produce philosophical works. From the
time of the Restoration he acquired a new
prominence; "Hobbism" became a byword for all that respectable society
ought to denounce. The young king, Hobbes's former pupil, now Charles
II, remembered Hobbes and called him to the court to grant him a
pension of £100. The king
was important in protecting Hobbes when, in 1666, the House
of
Commons introduced
a bill against atheism and profaneness. That same year, on 17 October
1666, it was ordered that the committee to which the bill was referred
"should be empowered to receive information touching such books as tend
to atheism, blasphemy and profaneness... in particular... the book of
Mr. Hobbes called the Leviathan". Hobbes was terrified at the
prospect of being labelled a heretic, and proceeded to burn some of his
compromising papers. At the same time, he examined the actual state of
the law of heresy.
The
results of his investigation were first announced in three short
Dialogues added as an Appendix to his Latin translation of
Leviathan, published at Amsterdam in 1668. In this appendix, Hobbes
aimed to show that, since the High
Court
of Commission had
been put down, there remained no court of heresy at all to which he was
amenable, and that nothing could be heresy except opposing the Nicene
Creed, which, he maintained, Leviathan did not do. The only
consequence that came of the bill was that Hobbes could never
thereafter publish anything in England on subjects relating to human
conduct. The 1668 edition of his works was printed in Amsterdam because
he could not obtain the censor's licence for its publication in
England. Other writings were not made public until after his death,
including Behemoth:
the History of the Causes of the Civil Wars of England and of the
Counsels and Artifices by which they were carried on from the year 1640
to the year 1662. For some time, Hobbes was not even allowed to
respond, whatever his enemies tried. Despite this, his reputation
abroad was formidable, and noble or learned foreigners who came to
England never forgot to pay their respects to the old philosopher. His final
works were a curious mixture: an autobiography in Latin verse in 1672,
and a translation of four books of the Odyssey into "rugged" English
rhymes that in 1673 led to a complete translation of both Iliad and Odyssey in 1675. In
October 1679, Hobbes suffered a bladder disorder, which was followed by
a paralytic stroke from which he died on 4 December 1679. He is said to
have uttered the last words "A great leap in the dark" in his final
moments of life. He was interred within St.
John the Baptist Church in Ault
Hucknall in Derbyshire, England. |