January 14, 2011 <Back to Index>
PAGE SPONSOR |
Alfred Tarski (January 14, 1901, Warsaw, Poland, Russian Empire – October 26, 1983, Berkeley, California) was a Polish logician and mathematician. Educated at the University of Warsaw and a member of the Lwow-Warsaw School of Logic and the Warsaw School of Mathematics and philosophy, he emigrated to the USA in 1939, and taught and carried out research in mathematics at the University of California, Berkeley, from 1942 until his death. A prolific author best known for his work on model theory, metamathematics, and algebraic logic, he also contributed to abstract algebra, topology, geometry, measure theory, mathematical logic, set theory, and analytic philosophy. Tarski's student Robert Vaught ranked Tarski as one of the four greatest logicians of all time, along with Aristotle, Kurt Gödel, and Gottlob Frege, although Tarski himself expressed great admiration for Charles Sanders Peirce. His biographers Anita and Solomon Feferman state
that, "Along with his contemporary, Kurt Gödel, he changed the
face of logic in the twentieth century, especially through his work on
the concept of truth and the theory of models." Alfred Tarski was born Alfred Teitelbaum (Polish spelling: "Tajtelbaum"), to parents who were Polish Jews in comfortable circumstances. He first manifested his mathematical abilities while in secondary school, at Warsaw's Szkoła Mazowiecka. Nevertheless, he entered the University of Warsaw in 1918 intending to study biology. After Poland regained independence in 1918, Warsaw University came under the leadership of Jan Łukasiewicz, Stanisław Leśniewski and Wacław Sierpiński and
quickly became a world leading research institution in logic,
foundational mathematics, and the philosophy of mathematics. Leśniewski
recognized Tarski's potential as a mathematician and persuaded him to
abandon biology. Henceforth Tarski attended courses taught by Łukasiewicz, Sierpiński, Stefan Mazurkiewicz and Tadeusz Kotarbiński,
and became the only person ever to complete a doctorate under
Leśniewski's supervision. Tarski and Leśniewski soon grew cool to each
other. However, in later life, Tarski reserved his warmest praise for Kotarbiński, as was mutual. In
1923, Alfred Teitelbaum and his brother Wacław changed their surname to
"Tarski", a name they invented because it sounded more Polish, was
simple to spell and pronounce, and seemed unused. (Years later, Alfred
met another Alfred Tarski in northern California.) The Tarski brothers
also converted to Roman Catholicism, Poland's dominant religion. Alfred did so even though he was an avowed atheist. Tarski
was a Polish nationalist who saw himself as a Pole and wished to be
fully accepted as such. In America, he spoke Polish at home. In
1929 Tarski married a fellow teacher Maria Witkowska, a Pole of
Catholic ancestry. She had worked as a courier for the army during
Poland's fight for independence. They had two children, a son Jan who
became a physicist, and a daughter Ina who married the mathematician Andrzej Ehrenfeucht. After
becoming the youngest person ever to complete a doctorate at Warsaw
University, Tarski taught logic at the Polish Pedagogical Institute,
mathematics and logic at the University, and served as Łukasiewicz's
assistant. Because these positions were poorly paid, Tarski also taught
mathematics at a Warsaw secondary school; before World War II, it was
not uncommon for European intellectuals of research caliber to teach
high school. Hence between 1923 and his departure for the United States
in 1939, Tarski not only wrote several textbooks and many papers, a
number of them ground-breaking, but also did so while supporting
himself primarily by teaching high-school mathematics. Tarski applied
for a chair of philosophy at Lwów University, but on Bertrand Russell's recommendation it was awarded to Leon Chwistek. In 1937 Tarski applied for a chair at Poznań University; but, the chair was abolished. In 1930, Tarski visited the University of Vienna, lectured to Karl Menger's
colloquium, and met Kurt Gödel. Thanks to a fellowship, he was
able to return to Vienna during the first half of 1935 to work with
Menger's research group. From Vienna he travelled to Paris to present
his ideas on truth at the first meeting of the Unity of Science movement, an outgrowth of the Vienna Circle.
Tarski's ties to this movement saved his life, because they resulted in
his being invited to address the Unity of Science Congress held in
September 1939 at Harvard University. Thus he left Poland in August 1939, on the last ship to sail from Poland for the United States before the German invasion of Poland and the outbreak of World War II.
Tarski left reluctantly, because Leśniewski had died a few months
before, creating a vacancy which Tarski hoped to fill. He was so
oblivious to the Nazi threat
that he left his wife and children in Warsaw; he did not see them again
until 1946. During the war, nearly all his extended family died at the
hands of the German occupying authorities. Once in the United States, Tarski held a number of temporary teaching and research positions: Harvard University (1939), City College of New York (1940), and thanks to a Guggenheim Fellowship, the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton (1942), where he again met Gödel. Tarski became an American citizen in 1945. In 1942, Tarski joined the Mathematics Department at the University of California, Berkeley,
where he spent the rest of his career. Although emeritus from 1968, he
taught until 1973 and supervised Ph.D. candidates until his death. At Berkeley, Tarski acquired a reputation as an awesome and demanding teacher, a fact noted by many observers: Indeed, Tarski supervised twenty-four Ph.D. dissertations including (in chronological order) those of Andrzej Mostowski, Bjarni Jónsson, Julia Robinson, Robert Vaught, Solomon Feferman, Richard Montague, James Donald Monk, Haim Gaifman, Donald Pigozzi and Roger Maddux, as well as Chen Chung Chang and Jerome Keisler, authors of Model Theory (1973), a classic text in the field. He also strongly influenced the dissertations of Alfred Lindenbaum, Dana Scott, and Steven Givant.
Five of Tarski's students were women, a remarkable fact given that men
represented an overwhelming majority of graduate students at the time. Tarski lectured at University College, London (1950, 1966), the Institut Henri Poincaré in Paris (1955), the Miller Institute for Basic Research in Science in Berkeley (1958 – 1960), the University of California at Los Angeles (1967), and the Pontifical Catholic University of Chile (1974 – 75). Among many distinctions garnered over the course of his career, Tarski was elected to the United States National Academy of Sciences, the British Academy and the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences, received honorary degrees from the Pontifical Catholic University of Chile in 1975, from Marseilles' Paul Cézanne University in 1977 and from the University of Calgary, as well as the Berkeley Citation in 1981. Tarski presided over the Association for Symbolic Logic, 1944–46, and the International Union for the History and Philosophy of Science, 1956-57. He was also an honorary editor of Algebra Universalis. Tarski's
mathematical interests were exceptionally broad for a mathematical
logician. His collected papers run to about 2500 pages, most of them on
mathematics, not logic. Tarski's first paper, published when he was 19 years old, was on set theory, a subject to which he returned throughout his life. In 1924, he and Stefan Banach proved that, if one accepts the Axiom of Choice, a ball can
be cut into a finite number of pieces, and then reassembled into a ball
of larger size, or alternatively it can be reassembled into two balls
whose sizes each equal that of the original one. This result is now
called the Banach–Tarski paradox. In A decision method for elementary algebra and geometry, Tarski showed, by the method of quantifier elimination, that the first-order theory of the real numbers under addition and multiplication is decidable.
(While this result appeared only in 1948, it dates back to 1930 and was
mentioned in Tarski (1931).) This is a very curious result, because Alonzo Church proved in 1936 that Peano arithmetic (effectively the theory Tarski proved decidable, except that the natural numbers replace the reals) is not decidable. Peano arithmetic is also incomplete by Gödel's incompleteness theorem. In his 1953 Undecidable theories, Tarski et al. showed that many mathematical systems, including lattice theory, abstract projective geometry, and closure algebras, are all undecidable. The theory of Abelian groups is decidable, but that of non-Abelian groups is not. In the 1920s and 30s, Tarski often taught high school geometry.
In 1929, he showed that much of Euclidean solid geometry could be
recast as a first-order theory whose individuals are spheres, a
primitive notion, a single primitive binary relation "is contained in",
and two axioms that, among other things, imply that containment partially orders the spheres. Relaxing the requirement that all individuals be spheres yields a formalization of mereology far easier to exposit than Lesniewski's variant. Starting in 1926, Tarski devised an original axiomatization for plane Euclidean geometry, one considerably more concise than Hilbert's. Tarski's axiomatization is a first-order theory devoid of set theory, whose individuals are points, and having only two primitive relations.
In 1930, he proved this theory decidable because it can be mapped into
another theory he had already proved decidable, namely his first-order
theory of the real numbers. Near the end of his life, Tarski wrote a
very long letter, published as Tarski and Givant (1999), summarizing
his work on geometry. Cardinal Algebras studied algebras whose models include the arithmetic of cardinal numbers. Ordinal Algebras sets out an algebra for the additive theory of order types. Cardinal, but not ordinal, addition commutes. In 1941, Tarski published an important paper on binary relations, which began the work on relation algebra and its metamathematics that
occupied Tarski and his students for much of the balance of his life.
While that exploration (and the closely related work of Roger Lyndon)
uncovered some important limitations of relation algebra, Tarski also
showed (Tarski and Givant 1987) that relation algebra can express most axiomatic set theory and Peano arithmetic. In the late 1940s, Tarski and his students devised cylindric algebras, which are to first-order logic what the two-element Boolean algebra is to classical sentential logic. This work culminated in two monographs by Tarski, Henkin, and Monk (1971, 1985). Tarski's
student, Vaught, has ranked Tarski as one of the four greatest
logicians of all time --- along with Aristotle, Gottlob Frege, and Kurt
Gödel. However, Tarski often expressed great admiration for Charles Sanders Peirce, particularly for his pioneering work in the logic of relations. Tarski produced axioms for logical consequence, and worked on deductive systems,
the algebra of logic, and the theory of definability. His semantic
methods, which culminated in the model theory he and a number of his
Berkeley students developed in the 1950s and 60s, radically transformed
Hilbert's proof-theoretic metamathematics. Tarski's
1936 article "On the concept of logical consequence" argued that the
conclusion of an argument will follow logically from its premises if
and only if every model of the premises is a model of the conclusion.
In 1937, he published a paper presenting clearly his views on the
nature and purpose of the deductive method, and the role of logic in
scientific studies. His high school and undergraduate teaching on logic
and axiomatics culminated in a classic short text, published first in
Polish, then in German translation, and finally in a 1941 English
translation as Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive Sciences. Tarski's 1969 "Truth and proof" considered both Gödel's incompleteness theorems and Tarski's undefinability theorem, and mulled over their consequences for the axiomatic method in mathematics. In
1933, Tarski published a very long (more than 100pp) paper in Polish,
titled "Pojęcie prawdy w językach nauk dedukcyjnych", setting out a
mathematical definition of truth for formal languages. The 1935 German
translation was titled "Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten
Sprachen", (The concept of truth in formalized languages), sometimes
shortened to "Wahrheitsbegriff". An English translation had to await
the 1956 first edition of the volume Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. This enormously cited paper is a landmark event in 20th century analytic philosophy, an important contribution to symbolic logic, semantics, and the philosophy of language. Some
recent philosophical debate examines the extent to which Tarski's
theory of truth for formalized languages can be seen as a correspondence theory of truth.
The debate centers on how to read Tarski's condition of material
adequacy for a truth definition. That condition requires that the truth
theory have the following as theorems for all sentences p of the
language for which truth is being defined: The debate amounts to whether to read sentences of this form, such as as expressing merely a deflationary theory of truth or as embodying truth as a more substantial property. In
1936, Tarski published Polish and German versions of a lecture he had
given the preceding year at the International Congress of Scientific
Philosophy in Paris. A new English translation of this paper (2002)
highlights the many differences between the German and Polish
versions of the paper, and corrects a number of mistranslations. This
publication set out the modern model-theoretic definition of (semantic) logical consequence, or at least the basis for it.
Whether Tarski's notion was entirely the modern one turns on whether he
intended to admit models with varying domains (and in particular,
models with domains of different cardinalities). This question is a matter of some debate in the current philosophical literature. Tarski
ends by pointing out that his definition of logical consequence depends
upon a division of terms into the logical and the extra-logical and he
expresses some skepticism that any such objective division will be
forthcoming. "What are Logical Notions?" can thus be viewed as
continuing "On the Concept of Logical Consequence". Another
theory of Tarski's attracting attention in the recent philosophical
literature is that outlined in his "What are Logical Notions?" (1986).
This is the published version of a talk that he gave in 1966; it
was edited without his direct involvement. In
the talk, Tarski proposed a demarcation of the logical operations
(which he calls "notions") from the non-logical. The suggested criteria
were derived from the Erlangen programme of the German 19th century Mathematician, Felix Klein.
(Mautner 1946, and possibly an article by the Portuguese mathematician
Sebastiao e Silva, anticipated Tarski in applying the Erlangen Program
to logic.) That program classified the various types of geometry (Euclidean geometry, affine geometry, topology,
etc.) by the type of one-one transformation of space onto itself that
left the objects of that geometrical theory invariant. (A one-to-one
transformation is a functional map of the space onto itself so that
every point of the space is associated with or mapped to one other
point of the space. So, "rotate 30 degrees" and "magnify by a factor of
2" are intuitive descriptions of simple uniform one-one
transformations.) Continuous transformations give rise to the objects
of topology, similarity transformations to those of Euclidean geometry,
and so on. As
the range of permissible transformations becomes broader, the range of
objects one is able to distinguish as preserved by the application of
the transformations becomes narrower. Similarity transformations are
fairly narrow (they preserve the relative distance between points) and
thus allow us to distinguish relatively many things (e.g., equilateral
triangles from non-equilateral triangles). Continuous transformations
(which can intuitively be thought of as transformations which allow
non-uniform stretching, compression, bending, and twisting, but no
ripping or glueing) allow us to distinguish a polygon from an annulus (ring
with a hole in the centre), but do not allow us to distinguish two
polygons from each other. Tarski's proposal was to demarcate the
logical notions by considering all possible one-to-one transformations (automorphisms) of a domain onto itself. By domain is meant the universe of discourse of a model for the semantic theory of a logic. If one identifies the truth value True
with the domain set and the truth-value False with the empty set, then
the following operations are counted as logical under the proposal: 1. Truth-functions: All truth-functions are admitted by the proposal. This includes, but is not limited to, all n-ary truth-functions for finite n. (It also admits of truth-functions with any infinite number of places.) 2. Individuals: No individuals, provided the domain has at least two members. 3. Predicates: 4. Quantifiers:
Tarski explicitly discusses only monadic quantifiers and points out
that all such numerical quantifiers are admitted under his proposal.
These include the standard universal and existential quantifiers as
well as numerical quantifiers such as "Exactly four", "Finitely many",
"Uncountably many", and "Between four and 9 million", for example.
While Tarski does not enter into the issue, it is also clear that
polyadic quantifiers are admitted under the proposal. These are
quantifiers like, given two predicates Fx and Gy, "More(x, y)", which says "More things have F than have G." 5. Set-Theoretic relations: Relations such as inclusion, intersection and union applied to subsets of the domain are logical in the present sense. 6. Set membership:
Tarski ended his lecture with a discussion of whether the set
membership relation counted as logical in his sense. (Given the
reduction of (most of) mathematics to set theory, this was, in effect,
the question of whether most or all of mathematics is a part of logic.)
He pointed out that set membership is logical if set theory is
developed along the lines of type theory, but is extralogical if set theory is set out axiomatically, as in the canonical Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. 7. Logical notions of higher order:
While Tarski confined his discussion to operations of first-order
logic, there is nothing about his proposal that necessarily restricts
it to first-order logic. (Tarski likely restricted his attention to
first-order notions as the talk was given to a non-technical audience.)
So, higher-order quantifiers and predicates are admitted as well. In
some ways the present proposal is the obverse of that of Lindenbaum and
Tarski (1936), who proved that all the logical operations of Russell and Whitehead's Principia Mathematica are
invariant under one-to-one transformations of the domain onto itself. Solomon Feferman and Vann McGee further
discussed Tarski's proposal in work published after his death. Feferman
raises problems for the proposal and suggests a cure: replacing
Tarski's preservation by automorphisms with preservation by arbitrary homomorphisms. In essence, this suggestion circumvents the difficulty Tarski's
proposal has in dealing with sameness of logical operation across
distinct domains of a given cardinality and across domains of distinct
cardinalities. Feferman's proposal results in a radical restriction of
logical terms as compared to Tarski's original proposal. In particular,
it ends up counting as logical only those operators of standard
first-order logic without identity. McGee
(1996) provides a precise account of what operations are logical in the
sense of Tarski's proposal in terms of expressibility in a language
that extends first-order logic by allowing arbitrarily long
conjunctions and disjunctions, and quantification over arbitrarily many
variables. "Arbitrarily" includes a countable infinity. |