January 16, 2011 <Back to Index>
PAGE SPONSOR |
Franz Clemens Honoratus Hermann Brentano (January 16, 1838 – March 17, 1917) was an influential German philosopher and psychologist whose influence was felt by other such luminaries as Sigmund Freud, Edmund Husserl, Kazimierz Twardowski and Alexius Meinong, who followed and adapted his views. Brentano was born at Marienberg am Rhein, near Boppard. He studied philosophy at the universities of Munich, Würzburg, Berlin (with Adolf Trendelenburg) and Münster. He had a special interest in Aristotle and scholastic philosophy. He wrote his dissertation in Tübingen On the manifold sense of Being in Aristotle. Subsequently he began to study theology and entered the seminary in Munich and then Würzburg and entered the Jesuit order. He was ordained a Catholic priest on August 6, 1864. In 1865/66 he wrote and defended his habilitation essay and thesis and began to lecture at the University of Würzburg. His students in this period included, among others, Carl Stumpf and Anton Marty. Between 1870 and 1873 Brentano was heavily involved in the debate on papal infallibility. A strong opponent of such dogma, he eventually gave up his priesthood and his tenure in 1873 and in 1879 left the church altogether. In 1874 Brentano published his major work: "Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint" and from 1874 to 1895 taught at the University of Vienna. Among his students were Edmund Husserl, Alexius Meinong, Christian von Ehrenfels, Rudolf Steiner, T.G. Masaryk, Sigmund Freud, Kazimierz Twardowski and many others (School of Brentano). While he began his career as a full ordinary professor, he was forced to give up both his Austrian citizenship and his professorship in 1880 in order to marry. He was permitted to return to the university only as a Privatdozent. After his retirement he moved to Florence in Italy, transferring to Zürich at the outbreak of the First World War, where he died in 1917.
Brentano is best known for his reintroduction of the concept of intentionality — a concept derived from scholastic philosophy — to contemporary philosophy in his lectures and in his work Psychologie vom Empirischen Standpunkte (Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint).
While often simplistically summarised as "aboutness" or the
relationship between mental acts and the external world, Brentano defined it as the main characteristic of mental phenomena, by which they could be distinguished from physical phenomena. Every mental phenomenon, every psychological act has content, is directed at an object (the intentional object).
Every belief, desire etc. has an object that they are about: the
believed, the desired. Brentano used the expression "intentional
inexistence" to indicate the status of the objects of thought in the
mind. The property of being intentional, of having an intentional
object, was the key feature to distinguish psychical phenomena and
physical phenomena, because, as Brentano defined it, physical phenomena
lacked the ability to generate original intentionality, and could only facilitate an intentional relationship in a second-hand manner, which he labeled derived intentionality. He is also well known for claiming that Wahrnehmung ist Falschnehmung ('perception
is misception' or literally 'truth-grasping is false-grasping') that is
to say perception is erroneous. In fact he maintained that external,
sensory perception could not tell us anything about the de facto existence
of the perceived world, which could simply be illusion. However, we can
be absolutely sure of our internal perception. When I hear a tone, I
cannot be completely sure that there is a tone in the real world, but I
am absolutely certain that I do hear. This awareness, of the fact that
I hear, is called internal perception. External perception, sensory
perception, can only yield hypotheses about the perceived world, but
not truth. Hence he and many of his pupils (in particular Carl Stumpf and Edmund Husserl) thought that the natural sciences could only yield hypotheses and never universal, absolute truths as in pure logic or mathematics. However, in a reprinting of his Psychologie vom Empirischen Standpunkte [Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint],
he recanted this previous view. He attempted to do so without reworking
the previous arguments within that work but it has been said that he
was wholly unsuccessful. The new view states that when we hear a sound,
we hear something from the external world; there are no physical
phenomena of internal perception. Of course, when he makes this change
he is not only recanting this portion (as he tried to maintain), he is
also recanting everything that he derived from the claim that internal
perception was flawless.
Brentano has a theory of judgment which is different from what is currently the predominant (Fregean) view. At the centre of Brentano’s theory of judgment lies the idea that a judgment depends on having a presentation, but this presentation does not have to be predicated. Even stronger: Brentano thought that predication is
not even sufficient for judgment, because there are judgments without a
predicational content. Another fundamental aspect of his theory is that
judgments are always existential.
This so-called existential claim implies that when someone is judging
that S is P he/she is judging that some S that is P exists. (Note that
Brentano denied the idea that all judgments are of the form: S is P
[and all other kinds of judgment which combine presentations]. Brentano
argued that there are also judgments arising from a single
presentation, e.g. “the planet Mars exists” has only one presentation.)
In Brentano’s own symbols, a judgment is always of the form: ‘+A’ (A
exists) or ‘-A’ (A does not exist). Combined with the third fundamental
claim of Brentano, the idea that all judgments are either positive
(judging that A exists) or negative (judging that A does not exist), we
have a complete picture of Brentano’s theory of judgment. So, imagine
that you doubt whether midgets exist or not. At that point you have a
presentation of midgets in your mind. When you judge that midgets do
not exist, then you are judging that the presentation you have does not
present something that exists. You do not have to utter that in words
or otherwise predicate that judgment. The whole judgment takes place in
the denial (or approval) of the existence of the presentation you have.
The problem of Brentano’s theory of judgment is not the idea that all
judgments are existential judgments (though it is sometimes a very
complex enterprise to transform an ordinary judgment into an
existential one), the real problem is that Brentano made no distinction
between object and
presentation. A presentation exists as an object in your mind. So you
cannot really judge that A does not exist, because if you do so you
also judge that the presentation is not there (which is impossible,
according to Brentano’s idea that all judgments have the object which
is judged as presentation). Twardowski acknowledged
this problem and solved it by denying that the object is equal to the
presentation. This is actually only a change within Brentano’s theory
of perception, but has a welcome consequence for the theory of
judgment, viz. that you can have a presentation (which exists) but at
the same time judge that the object does not exist. |