March 10, 2016
<Back to Index>
This page is sponsored by:
PAGE SPONSOR |
Nicholas of Autrecourt (in French Nicholas d'Autrécourt; in Latin Nicolaus de Autricuria or Nicolaus de Ultricuria; ca. 1299, Autrecourt – 16 or 17 July 1369, Metz) was a French medieval philosopher and Scholastic theologian. Born in Autrecourt, near Verdun, he was known principally for developing skepticism to extreme logical conclusions. He is sometimes considered the sole genuinely skeptic philosopher of medieval times. Like David Hume centuries
later, he founded his skeptical position on arguments that knowledge
claims were not "reducible to the first principle", that is, that it was
not contradictory to deny them. Whether he was committed to these conclusions is unclear, but on 19 May 1346 they were condemned by Pope Clement VI as heretical and his books publicly burned. In
the 14th century, Nicholas of Autrecourt considered that matter, space,
and time were all made up of indivisible atoms, points, and instants
and that all generation and corruption took place by the rearrangement
of material atoms. The similarities of his ideas with those of al - Ghazali suggest
that Nicholas was familiar with the work of al - Ghazali, who was known
as "Algazel" in Europe, either directly or indirectly through Averroes.
Nicholas of Autrecourt
The
most striking feature of Autrecourt's academic career is his
condemnation in 1347. In almost every history of medieval philosophy,
his censure is presented as one of the most important events in
fourteenth century Paris. In the older literature, Autrecourt's views
have become linked to allegedly skeptical tendencies in scholastic
thought, and have been unduly shadowed by assumptions about their
relation to the views of William of Ockham. Over the last two decades,
however, it has become apparent that the study of Autrecourt's thought
has been wrongly placed in the larger context of the battle against
Ockhamism at the University of Paris in the years 1339 - 1347. Although
Autrecourt was no skeptic — on the contrary, he attacked the “Academics”
or ancient Skeptics — his philosophical stance challenges the
prevailing Aristotelian tradition. In particular, Autrecourt rejected
some of the main tenets of scholastic metaphysics and epistemology, such
as the substance - accident structure of reality and the principle of
causality. 1. LifeAs
is the case with many medieval thinkers, Autrecourt's biographical
details are few. What we know about his intellectual life has to be
reconstructed using dates that are attached to the handful of documents
in which he is mentioned. One of these is a record from sometime between
1333 - 36, indicating that he served as prior at the Collège de
Sorbonne. Another important document is a papal letter of 1338 in which
Benedict XII confers upon him the function of canon at Metz Cathedral,
and refers to him as a master of arts and bachelor of theology and civil
law. Evidently, however, Autrecourt did not claim his prebendary
stipend until after his trial in 1347. On the basis of such
references, Autrecourt's date of birth can be placed sometime between
1295 - 98. He originated from Autrécourt in the diocese of Verdun,
and was probably a student in the arts faculty at Paris, belonging to
either the English, or, more likely, the French nation. His master's
degree in arts can be dated around 1318 - 20. While a student, he must
have come across such famous masters as John of Jandun, Marsilius of
Padua, Thomas Wilton, Walter Burley, Bartholomew of Bruges, or Siger of
Courtrai. Since his law degree was in civil rather than canon law, he
must have left Paris at some point for a minimum of five years, probably
to study at Orléans, Avignon, or Montpellier. His
membership in the Collège de Sorbonne places Autrecourt back in
Paris in the 1330s as a student of theology. On November 21, 1340, Pope
Benedict XII summoned him from Paris to Avignon to respond to
allegations of false teaching. In his letter, the pope refers to
Autrecourt as a licentiatus in
theology, meaning that Autrecourt had fullfilled the formal
requirements for the theology degree, e.g., lecturing on the Bible and
the Sentences.
But does it also mean that he was a full - fledged master of theology? The
question is controversial. In the judgment at his trial, it was
stipulated that Autrecourt could only obtain “magisterial honor and
degree” after special permission from the Apostolic See, which seems to
imply that he was not allowed to progress to inception in theology (the
ceremony in which the magisterial honors would be conferred) until the
pope decided otherwise. Moreover, there are no records referring to
Autrecourt as a master in theology. This suggests that Autrecourt remained a licentiatus in
theology when he moved on to Metz to take his position as canon (and
later dean) of the cathedral chapter. He died in 1369, on either July 16
or 17. Another scenario is that Autrecourt's licenciate in theology was
removed as a result of his conviction and that it had been restored by
the time that he was confirmed as dean of the chapter at Metz. 2. Autrecourt's Trial and ConvictionAutrecourt's
time of trial began in 1340 when he was first summoned to appear before
the papal court in Avignon and lasted until his conviction in 1346. An
extensive, though as yet incomplete, dossier of the judicial process at
Avignon has been preserved in the form of an instrumentum publicum (actually,
a draft copy thereof), which served as a model for the preparation of
the official record of the process. The papal dossier contains copies of
a number of records that played a role during earlier stages of
Autrecourt's trial, and gives an account (narratio) of the judicial proceedings from the moment Cardinal Curti, the judge, took over the investigation. The
record specifies the charges and summarizes the false teachings of
which Autrecourt was accused in the form of four lists, together totalling 66 erroneous propositions or “articles” (articuli).
The articles were culled from Autrecourt's writings and oral teachings.
On the basis of this record, it would appear that the papal commissions
of Pope Clement VI and Cardinal Curti used evidence from earlier
proceedings at the University of Paris and Autrecourt's response to this
evidence to reach their verdicts. If this scenario is correct, it
raises two obvious questions: why was Autrecourt's trial transferred
from Paris to Avignon, and how did it begin in the first place?
Unfortunately, the surviving historical evidence is insufficient to
answer either question. The commission of prelates and
theologians, which under the chairmanship of Cardinal Curti had
discussed all of the articles attributed to Autrecourt, came to the
conclusion that they contained many false, dangerous, presumptuous,
suspect, erroneous, and heretical statements. For this reason,
Autrecourt's writings were ordered burned either at
Pré - aux - Clercs or Pré - de - Saint - Germain at Paris at an
unspecified future date. Moreover, Autrecourt was ordered to publicly
recant several of the articles specified in the legal record. These
recantations and declarations, which Autrecourt was first required to
make at the palace of Cardinal Curti in Avignon, had to be repeated at
the University of Paris. Autrecourt's recantation at the papal court
took place before May 19, 1346. The exact date is unknown because it was
left blank in the draft prepared by the notary Bernard. In addition to
the recantation, Autrecourt was declared unworthy to ascend to the
magisterial rank in the theological faculty. Anyone in possession of the
authority to present or promote Autrecourt to the magisterium of the
faculty of theology was thereafter forbidden to do so. The
Parisian part of the sentence was fulfilled the following year. On
November, 20, 1347 the regent and non - regent masters of the university
met at the Church of Saint - Mathurin, where papal letters and the process
“concerning certain articles” were read. This material had been brought
from Avignon by Autrecourt himself. On November 25, Autrecourt recanted
the four confessed articles and the articles from the letter “Ve michi”
in the Church of the Dominicans, and publicly declared that the
propositions contained in the other two lists were wrong. In addition,
he burned these articles and a treatise, most likely the Exigit ordo. The public reading of the instrumentum and
the recantation served an important purpose. It not only made the
sentence effective, but also informed the scholarly community of
Autrecourt's errors and of the punishments set out in the instrumentum, which they would incur if they were to teach the censured errors. Years
later, scholars such as John Buridan, Marsilius of Inghen, and
André of Neufchâteau (Andreas de Novo Castro) cited the
condemned erroneous propositions as the articuli cardinalis (albi). 3. WritingsAutrecourt's
oeuvre is not large. There is a correspondence with the Franciscan
theologian Bernard of Arezzo, and with a certain Master Giles (possibly
Giles of Feno), and a treatise that has come to be known as the Exigit ordo.
Furthermore, we have a theological question dealing with the intension
and remission of forms and the problem of minima and maxima (utrum visio alicuius rei naturalis possit naturali intendi [Could the vision of any natural thing be naturally intensified?]). Autrecourt
wrote nine letters to Bernard of Arezzo, only two of which survive. In
addition, there is one letter from master Giles addressed to Autrecourt,
along with a brief response by the latter, which, however, breaks off
in mid - sentence. The correspondence has been preserved in two manuscript
copies from the intellectual milieu of the Collège de Sorbonne.
Together the letters form a small dossier, the central item of which is
the letter from Master Giles. Apparently, the only reason the two
letters to Bernard were copied was because they are mentioned in the
letter from Master Giles. The correspondence between Autrecourt and
Bernard of Arezzo is much earlier, dating from the time when both were
theology students, engaged as opponents in each other's Principia, i.e., inaugural lecture on the Sentences. They can be dated between October 1335 and June 1336, although both Principia are now lost. There is no evidence that Autrecourt ever actually wrote a commentary on the Sentences, which, in any case was not a formal requirement for obtaining a degree. The theme of the discussion in the Principia and
the letters to Bernard of Arezzo is the validity of Aristotle's
principle of non - contradiction, as presented in Book IV of the Metaphysics. The Exigit ordo is the fruit of Autrecourt's teaching in the arts faculty. In the first of its two prologues, it is addressed to the reverendi patres,
i.e., to the theologians in religious orders. Instead of expounding his
views in commentaries on Aristotle's texts, Autrecourt chose to write an
independent treatise discussing issues pertaining to natural
philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology, philosophical psychology, and
ethics, and engaging in debate with unnamed contemporaries. The work is
not a neat sequence of chapters or questions with pro and con arguments.
It has been suggested that the Exigit was
a draft version in which Autrecourt had penned ideas, arguments and
fragments of disputations that were awaiting their final ordering. The
work was completed in the years 1333 - 35, at which time Autrecourt was
preparing his commentary on the Sentences.
For financial reasons, Autrecourt taught in the arts faculty while he
was enrolled as a student in theology. Possibly, he even wrote the Exigit after he commented on the Sentences, but before 1340, when he was summoned to Avignon. The Exigit ordo is also known as the Tractatus universalis (Universal Treatise). The latter title is actually a misreading of the first two words of the treatise, “tractatus utilis”
(useful treatise). It has been preserved in a single manuscript copy,
which, like the Giles letter, breaks off in mid - sentence. It is divided
into two prologues, two treatises, and several chapters, which,
unfortunately, the scribe has placed in the wrong order. The Latin
edition and English translation both preserve the order of the medieval manuscript without correction. The theological question is a report (reportatio)
of a theological disputation in which Autrecourt served as respondent
to the objections. Although the presiding master of a disputation would
usually have to be considered its real author, matters may be different here. Since it is a reportatio — i.e., a text which, unlike an ordinatio,
was not subjected to later editing by the master himself — Autrecourt's
views probably appear in unadulterated form. The question was disputed
between 1336 - 39, and has been little studied by scholars. 4. EpistemologyCentral to Autrecourt's teaching is the view that all evident knowledge (with the exception of the certitude of faith) must be reducible to the first principle (primum principium),
i.e., to the principle of non - contradiction. An inference yields
evident knowledge only when the affirmation of its antecedent and the
negation of its consequent are contradictory. This means that the
antecedent and the consequent, or, more precisely, what is signified by
the antecedent and the consequent, must be identical, “because if this
were not the case, it would not be immediately evident that the
antecedent and the opposite of the consequent cannot stand together
without contradiction.” It is in the context of this theory that
Autrecourt launches an attack on our claim to have certain knowledge of
the existence of substances and causal relations. If A and B are two
distinct entities, he says, one cannot infer with certainty (knowledge
of) the existence of A from that of B or vice versa, for the affirmation
of the one and the denial of the other does not result in a
contradiction. On the basis of this principle, one may not infer
(knowledge of) the existence of effects from knowledge of their causes,
nor (knowledge of) the existence of substances from knowledge of their
accidents. Autrecourt's theory about the evidentness of inferences was
contested by his contemporaries and should be understood in the light of
the late medieval theory of consequences. This view runs contrary
to the Aristotelian position, according to which causal relations
really exist and are discoverable by means of induction, so that the
existence of substances can be inferred from the perceptible accidents
inhering in them. The upshot of Autrecourt's view is that we do not have
experience of causal relations or substances, nor does logic provide
certain knowledge of them. There are no logical reasons to assume that
there is an evident relation between a cause and an effect, or between a
substance and an accident. The position outlined above is
developed in Autrecourt's correspondence. It has led historians of
philosophy to characterize him as the most important, if not the only,
“real” representative of medieval scepticism, as “the medieval Hume”, to
use Hastings Rashdall's epithet. On closer inspection, however, it
turns out that Autrecourt's scepticism is reserved for rationalist
claims about the truth of our commitments to causality and substance,
concepts for which we have no empirical proof. It is now generally
agreed that he is not a sceptic at all when it comes to defending the
reliability of sense - perception. In his Letter to Bernard,
Autrecourt takes on Bernard of Arezzo, who had argued that the
intellect is neither certain of the existence of those things of which
it has a clear intuitive cognition, nor of its own acts. Autrecourt
reveals the full implications of this position by pointing out to
Bernard that “you are not certain of those things which are outside of
you. And so you do not know if you are in the sky or on earth, in fire
or in water... Similarly, you do not know what things exist in your
immediate surroundings, such as whether you have a head, a beard, hair,
and the like.” He concludes that Bernard's stance is even worse than that of “the Academics,” that is, the ancient Skeptics. 5. MetaphysicsTo
Bernard's skeptical challenges Autrecourt replies that sense experience
is reliable. This theme is not further developed in the letters to
Bernard, however. For discussion of this topic we must turn to the Exigit ordo. In one section of this treatise, which is reminiscent of Aristotle's Metaphysics IV,
5, Autrecourt addresses one of the central issues of metaphysics,
namely the relation between appearance and reality. He addresses
Protagoras' view that whatever is apparent is true: An omne illud quod apparet sit? (Does everything that appears exist?). Autrecourt
defends the thesis that what appears, is, and that what appears true,
is true. He finds this view more plausible than its opposite, viz., that
the intellect cannot possess certitude. Autrecourt does not have a
meta - theory in which he defends his model of certain knowledge against
alternative theories. His appeal that his theory is the more probable
one, however, saves him from charges of dogmatism. His concept of
appearance plays a key role in his doctrine of certain knowledge. It is
used in a phenomenological sense, to describe perceptual experiences.
According to Autrecourt, the intellect is certain of everything that is
evident to it in the final analysis. This is the case for everything
that appears in a proper sense (apparet proprie), i.e., that appears clearly in an act of the external senses (in actu sensuum exteriorum).
He identifies appearances with the objects of immediate sensory
experience, which are considered evident. In this way, he implies that
sense perception is a reliable source of truth, i.e., that the apparent
properties of an object are its actual properties. But is sense
perception reliable? Perceptual errors and dreams seem to indicate that
things are not always as they seem. Autrecourt discusses several
sceptical doubts (dubia), versions of what would later be
called the “argument from illusion” and the “argument from dreaming”.
These arguments work from the common sense assumption that things often
appear to be other than they are: e.g., sweet food can appear bitter, a
white object can appear red, in sleep it can seem to someone that he is
flying through the air or fighting the Saracens. Autrecourt
responds to these sceptical doubts by distinguishing between appearance
and judgment. Appearances are always veridical: experience cannot be
other than it is. However, judgments made from experience can be
erroneous, especially if they are based on images rather than on what is
perceived “in the full light.” In other words, Autrecourt denies any
conflict of appearances. Those not “in the full light” are not in
themselves misperceptions because the experiences themselves are not
illusory. They merely fail to give us the real properties of the object
perceived. Potential conflict creeps in at the level of judgment, where
ontological claims are made on the basis of appearances. Only those
appearances that are “in the full light” reveal the true properties of
the perceived object, and only they can provide the basis for true
judgments. Appearances of objects that do not come to the perceiver “in
the full light” are incomplete or contaminated, as if the observer were
looking into a mirror. In other words, Autrecourt carefully
distinguishes between ‘x appears F’ from ‘x is F’, for even if x is not really F, it can still appear F and cause someone to believe that it is F. In this way, illusions and dreams turn into mistaken beliefs. Only clear appearances (apparentiae clarae) can cause veridical judgments. A
final topic taken up by Autrecourt in this context is the problem of
the criterion: How can one discriminate between appearances that provide
the basis for true judgments and those that do not? Like Aristotle, he
holds that appearances from what we perceive under “normal” conditions
cause true judgments. Also like Aristotle, he asserts that there is no
further proof that the criterion on which the distinction between
veridical and false judgments rests is correct. Both dismiss worries
about the justification of the criterion as absurd. In the words of
Autrecourt: “One must accept as true what appears in the full light.
Now, concerning the minor premise of this argument, how can you have
certainty? … One way of answering this would be to say that there is no
way of proving the conclusion, but that the concept of certitude which
is present comes as a certain natural consequence, and not as a
conclusion. An example, among others, is that white and black are
different. This concept of their difference is not gotten by way of
conclusion.” The reason why our senses can give us veridical
access to the objects is, because these objects determine the contents
of what appears. Autrecourt believes that there is a necessary
connection between the mental act and the object of which it is a
mental act. The object “configurates” the mental act, which becomes
identical to it. The metaphysical foundation of this theory is
Autrecourt's realism: he assumes that the same universal nature
manifests itself in numerically different objects in the world, and in
the mind, although in the latter in a different mode of being (secundum aliud esse objectivum). 6. Natural PhilosophyThe
point of departure for Autrecourt's physics is a thesis which strikes
him as more probable than its opposite, namely that all things are
eternal. Autrecourt assures the reader that he is speaking as a natural
philosopher, and that he is not contradicting Catholic faith. One of the
implications of his thesis is that there is no generation or corruption
in the universe. Autrecourt refutes Averroes's (and Aristotle's)
doctrine of prime matter in which substantial forms are generated and
corrupted. He replaces the theory of hylemorphism, which attributes the
coming - to - be and passing - away of properties and of objects to forms that
begin and cease to exist in matter, by atomism. Change in the natural
world is caused by the movement of atoms. These atoms are to be
understood as infinitely small parcels of matter which have properties. As
Autrecourt explicitly indicates, his discussion of the eternity of
things is linked to his views on motion and on atomism. For this reason,
he places the section on the divisibility of matter in between his
treatment of eternity and of motion, “because some of the points to be
raised about indivisibles will prepare us for the question of movement”.
What Autrecourt means is that a number of arguments about the
divisibility of space and time involve moving objects. Autrecourt
opens his discussion of atoms or indivisibles by restating Aristotle's
position that no continuum is composed of indivisibles. He presents five
arguments in support of this thesis, and places beside them his own
counterarguments, which are meant to prove “with sufficient probability”
the opposite conclusion. The section makes clear that Autrecourt is
familiar with the contemporary debates at Paris about the divisibility
of the continuum. It is not possible, however, to identify his
opponents, and at times his discussion lacks coherence. In keeping with
this atomistic view, he also holds that space and time consist of
indivisible units, viz., points and instants, respectively. The
discussion of motion, which focuses on its ontological status, is placed
in the larger context of a discussion of quantity. The reason is, that
motion is one particular type of quantity, namely successive quantity
(as distinct from permanent quantity). Autrecourt argues that material
substance and its quantity are not distinct. The same holds true for
other characteristic properties of a substance, the sensible qualities:
they are not distinct from their substance. Autrecourt claims, for
instance, that fire and its heat and water and its coldness are not
distinct. At the background of this section is the late - medieval debate
about the basic ontological categories, induced by Aristotle's Categories and Metaphysics.
Given these preliminaries, it comes as no surprise that Autrecourt also
defends the thesis that motion is not distinct from the mobile object. Autrecourt
argues that motion is not a thing distinct from the moving object.
Following Ockham, he rejects the idea that motion is a positive thing
inhering in the mobile object. Thus, the loss of motion should not be
described as the destruction or corruption of an entity, and the
eternity doctrine is saved. 7. SemanticsAutrecourt did not leave any logical writings, nor does he discuss logic or semantics in the Exigit ordo or
in his correspondence. However, from his theological question and a few
of the censured articles it is clear that he was familiar with the
logical debates of his time. According to one of the articles,
Autrecourt claimed that the proposition “Man is an animal” is not
necessary according to the faith, because in that sense one does not
attend to the necessary connection between its terms. The article should
be seen against the background of the sophism “Man is an animal”, which
received considerable attention in the thirteenth and fourteenth
centuries. It served to clarify the relation between meaning (significatio) and reference (suppositio) by investigating the verification of propositions concerning empty
classes. Would the proposition “Man is an animal” still be true if no
man exists? This article suggests that Autrecourt may have denied any
form of natural and metaphysical necessity, and for this reason was
condemned.
Five other articles that turn up in Autreourt's condemnation concern the complexe significabile,
or what is signified by an entire proposition. According to adherents
of the doctrine such as Adam Wodeham and Gregory of Rimini, the object
of knowledge is not the proposition, or the things (res) referred to in the external world, but “that which is signified” by the proposition (complexe significabile). One of the problems raised by this theory concerned the ontological status of the complexe significabile: Is it something (aliquid) or nothing (nihil)? Echoes of this and other debates can be found in these articles.
|