April 02, 2020 <Back to Index>
PAGE SPONSOR |
Democritus (Greek: Δημόκριτος, "chosen of the people") (ca. 460 BC – ca. 370 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosopher born in Abdera, Thrace, Greece. He was an influential pre - Socratic philosopher and pupil of Leucippus, who formulated an atomic theory for the cosmos. His exact contributions are difficult to disentangle from his mentor Leucippus, as they are often mentioned together in texts. Their speculation on atoms, taken from Leucippus, bears a passing and partial resemblance to the nineteenth century understanding of atomic structure that has led some to regard Democritus as more of a scientist than other Greek philosophers; however their ideas rested on very different bases. Largely ignored in ancient Athens, Democritus was nevertheless well known to his fellow northern born philosopher Aristotle. Plato is said to have disliked him so much that he wished all his books burned. Many consider Democritus to be the "father of modern science". Democritus
was born in the city of Abdera in Thrace, an Ionian colony
of Teos, although some called him a Milesian. He was born in the
80th Olympiad (460 – 457 BC) according to Apollodorus of
Athens, and although Thrasyllus placed his birth in 470
BC, the later date is probably more likely.
John Burnet has argued that the date of 460 is "too
early", since according to Diogenes Laërtius ix.41,
Democritus said that he was a "young man (neos)"
during Anaxagoras' old age (circa 440 – 428). It was said
that Democritus' father was so wealthy that he received
Xerxes on his march through Abdera. Democritus spent the
inheritance which his father left him on travels into
distant countries, to satisfy his thirst for knowledge. He
traveled to Asia, and was even said to have reached India
and Ethiopia. We know that he wrote on Babylon and Meroe; he must also have visited Egypt, and Diodorus Siculus states that he lived there for five years. He himself declared that among his contemporaries none had made greater journeys, seen more countries, and met more scholars than himself. He particularly mentions the Egyptian mathematicians, whose knowledge he praises. Theophrastus, too, spoke of him as a man who had seen many countries. During his travels, according to Diogenes Laërtius, he became acquainted with the Chaldean magi. A certain "Ostanes", one of the magi accompanying Xerxes was also said to have taught him. After returning to his native land he occupied himself
with natural philosophy. He traveled throughout Greece to
acquire a knowledge of its culture. He mentions many Greek
philosophers in his writings, and his wealth enabled him
to purchase their writings. Leucippus, the founder of the
atomism, was the greatest influence upon him. He also
praises Anaxagoras.
Diogenes Laertius says that he was friends with
Hippocrates.
He may have been acquainted with Socrates, but Plato does
not mention him and Democritus himself is quoted as
saying, "I came to Athens and no one knew me."
Aristotle placed him among the pre - Socratic natural
philosophers. The many anecdotes about Democritus, especially in Diogenes Laërtius, attest to his disinterest, modesty and simplicity, and show that he lived exclusively for his studies. One story has him deliberately blinding himself in order to be less disturbed in his pursuits; it may well be true that he lost his sight in old age. He was cheerful, and was always ready to see the comical side of life, which later writers took to mean that he always laughed at the foolishness of people. He was highly esteemed by his fellow citizens, "because," as Diogenes Laërtius says, "he had foretold them some things which events proved to be true," which may refer to his knowledge of natural phenomena. According to Diodorus Siculus, Democritus died at the age of 90, which would put his death around 370 BC, but other writers have him living to 104, or even 109. Popularly known as the Laughing Philosopher (for laughing at human follies), the terms Abderitan laughter, which means scoffing, incessant laughter, and Abderite, which means a scoffer, are derived from Democritus. To his fellow citizens he was also known as "The Mocker". Democritus followed in the tradition of Leucippus, who
seems to have come from Miletus, and he carried on the
scientific rationalist philosophy associated with that
city. They were both strict determinists and thorough
materialists, believing everything to be the result of
natural laws. Unlike Aristotle or Plato, the atomists attempted to explain
the world without reasoning to purpose, prime
mover, or final cause. For the atomists
questions should be answered with a mechanistic
explanation ("What earlier circumstances caused this
event?"), while their opponents search for explanations
which, in addition to the material and mechanistic, also
included the formal and teleological ("What purpose did
this event serve?"). Modern science has focused on
mechanistic questions, which have led to scientific
knowledge, especially in physics, while teleological
questions can be useful in biology, in adaptationist
reasoning at providing proximate explanations, though the
deeper evolutionary explanations are often held to be
thoroughly mechanistic. The atomists looked exclusively
for mechanistic questions, and only admitted mechanistic
answers. Their successors until the Renaissance became
occupied with the teleological question, which arguably
hindered progress. The theory of Democritus and Leucippus held that everything is composed of "atoms", which are physically, but not geometrically, indivisible; that between atoms lies empty space; that atoms are indestructible; have always been, and always will be, in motion; that there are an infinite number of atoms, and kinds of atoms, which differ in shape, and size. Of the mass of atoms, Democritus said "The more any indivisible exceeds, the heavier it is." But his exact position on weight of atoms is disputed. Leucippus is widely credited with being the first to develop the theory of atomism, although Isaac Newton preferred to credit the obscure Moschus the Phoenician (whom he believed to be the biblical Moses) as the inventor of the idea on the authority of Posidonius and Strabo. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy notes, "This theologically motivated view does not seem to claim much historical evidence, however." Democritus, along with Leucippus and Epicurus, proposed the earliest views on the shapes and connectivity of atoms. They reasoned that the solidness of the material corresponded to the shape of the atoms involved. Thus, iron atoms are solid and strong with hooks that lock them into a solid; water atoms are smooth and slippery; salt atoms, because of their taste, are sharp and pointed; and air atoms are light and whirling, pervading all other materials. Democritus was the main proponent of this view. Using analogies from our sense experiences, he gave a picture or an image of an atom that distinguished them from each other by their shape, their size, and the arrangement of their parts. Moreover, connections were explained by material links in which single atoms were supplied with attachments: some with hooks and eyes others with balls and sockets. The Democritean atom is an inert solid (merely excluding other bodies from its volume) that interacts with other atoms mechanically. In contrast, modern, quantum mechanical atoms interact via electric and magnetic force fields and are far from inert. The theory of the atomists appears to be more nearly
aligned with that of modern science than any other theory
of antiquity. However, the similarity with modern concepts
of science can be confusing when trying to understand
where the hypothesis came from. It is obvious that
classical atomists would never have had a solid empirical
basis for our modern concepts of atoms and molecules.
Bertrand Russell states that they just hit on a lucky
hypothesis, only recently confirmed by evidence. However
Lucretius, describing atomism in his De rerum natura
gives very clear and compelling empirical arguments for
the original atomist theory. He observes that any material
is subject to irreversible decay. Through time, even hard
rocks are slowly worn down by drops of water. Things have
the tendency to get mixed up: mix water with soil and you
get mud, that will usually not un-mix by itself. Wood
decays. However, we see in nature and technology that
there are mechanisms to recreate 'pure' materials like
water, air, metals. The seed of an oak will grow out into
an oak tree, made of similar wood as historical oak trees,
the wood of which has already decayed. The conclusion is
that many properties of materials must derive from
something inside, that will itself never decay, something
that stores for eternity the same inherent, indivisible
properties. The basic question is: why has everything in
the world not yet decayed, and how can exactly the same
materials, plants, animals be recreated again and again?
One obvious solution to explain how indivisible properties
can be conveyed in a way not easily visible to human
senses, is to hypothesize the existence of 'atoms'. These
classical 'atoms' are nearer to our modern concept of
'molecule' than to the atoms of modern science. The other
big point of classical atomism is that there must be a lot
of open space between these 'atoms': the void. Lucretius
gives reasonable arguments that the void is absolutely
necessary to explain how gasses and fluids can change
shape, flow, while metals can be molded, without changing
the basic material properties The atomistic void hypothesis was a response to the paradoxes of Parmenides and Zeno, the founders of metaphysical logic, who put forth difficult to answer arguments in favor of the idea that there can be no movement. They held that any movement would require a void — which is nothing — but a nothing cannot exist. The Parmenidean position was "You say there 'is' a void; therefore the void is not nothing; therefore there is not the void." The position of Parmenides appeared validated by the observation that where there seems to be nothing there is air, and indeed even where there is not matter there is something, for instance light waves. The atomists agreed that motion required a void, but
simply ignored the argument of Parmenides on the grounds
that motion was an observable fact. Therefore, they
asserted, there must be a void. This idea survived in a
refined version as Newton's theory of absolute space, which met the
logical requirements of attributing reality to not -
being. Einstein's theory of relativity provided a new
answer to Parmenides and Zeno, with the insight that space
by itself is relative and cannot be separated from time as
part of a generally curved space - time manifold.
Consequently, Newton's refinement is now considered
superfluous. The knowledge of truth according to Democritus is difficult, since the perception through the senses is subjective. As from the same senses derive different impressions for each individual, then through the sense - impressions we cannot judge the truth. We can only interpret the sense data through the intellect and grasp the truth, because the truth (aletheia) is at the bottom (en bythoe).
There are two kinds of knowing, the one he calls “legitimate” (gnesie: genuine) and the other “bastard” (skotie: obscure). The “bastard” knowledge is concerned with the perception through the senses, therefore it is insufficient and subjective. The reason is that the sense - perception is due to the effluences of the atoms (aporroai) from the objects to the senses. When these different shapes of atoms come to us, they stimulate our senses according to their shape, and our sense - impressions arise from those stimulations. The second sort of knowledge, the “legitimate” one, can be achieved through the intellect, in other words, all the sense - data from the “bastard” must be elaborated through reasoning. In this way one can get away from the false perception of the “bastard” knowledge and grasp the truth through the inductive reasoning. After taking into account the sense - impressions, one can examine the causes of the appearances, draw conclusions about the laws that govern the appearances, and discover the causality (aetiologia) by which they are related. This is the procedure of thought from the parts to the whole or else from the apparent to non - apparent (inductive reasoning). This is one example of why Democritus is considered to be an early scientific thinker. The process is reminiscent of that by which science gathers its conclusions.
The ethics and politics of Democritus come to us mostly in the form of maxims. He says that "Equality is everywhere noble," but he is not encompassing enough to include women or slaves in this sentiment. Poverty in a democracy is better than prosperity under tyrants, for the same reason one is to prefer liberty over slavery. Those in power should "take it upon themselves to lend to the poor and to aid them and to favor them, then is there pity and no isolation but companionship and mutual defense and concord among the citizens and other good things too many to catalog." Money when used with sense leads to generosity and charity, while money used in folly leads to a common expense for the whole society - excessive hoarding of money for one's children is avarice. While making money is not useless, he says, doing so as a result of wrong doing is the "worst of all things." He is on the whole ambivalent towards wealth, and values it much less than self sufficiency. He disliked violence but was not a pacifist: he urged cities to be prepared for war, and believed that a society had the right to execute a criminal or enemy so long as this did not violate some law, treaty, or oath. Goodness, he believed, came more from practice and discipline than from innate human nature. He believed that one should distance oneself from the wicked, stating that such association increases disposition to vice. Anger, while difficult to control, must be mastered in order for one to be rational. Those who take pleasure from the disasters of their neighbors fail to understand that their fortunes are tied to the society in which they live, and they rob themselves of any joy of their own. He advocated a life of contentment with as little grief as possible, which he said could not be achieved through either idleness or preoccupation with worldly pleasures. Contentment would be gained, he said, through moderation and a measured life; to be content one must set their judgment on the possible and be satisfied with what one has — giving little thought to envy or admiration. Democritus approved of extravagance on occasion, as he held that feasts and celebrations were necessary for joy and relaxation. He considers education to be the noblest of pursuits, but cautioned that learning without sense leads to error.
Democritus was also a pioneer of mathematics and
geometry in particular. We only know this through
citations of his works (titled On Numbers, On
Geometrics, On Tangencies, On Mapping,
and On Irrationals) in other writings, since most
of Democritus' body of work did not survive the Middle
Ages. Democritus was among the first to observe that a
cone or pyramid has one - third the volume of a cylinder
or prism respectively with the same base and height. Also,
a cone divided in a plane parallel to its base produces
two surfaces. He pointed out that if the two surfaces are
commensurate with each other, then the shape of the body
would appear to be a cylinder, as it is composed of equal
rather than unequal circles. However, if the surfaces are
not commensurate, then the side of a cone is not smooth
but jagged like a series of steps. His work on nature is known through citations of his books on the subjects, On the Nature of Man, On Flesh (two books), On Mind, On the Senses, On Flavors, On Colors, Causes concerned with Seeds and Plants and Fruits, and Causes concerned with Animals (three books). He spent much of his life experimenting with and examining plants and minerals, and wrote at length on many scientific topics. Democritus thought that the first humans lived an anarchic and animal sort of life, going out to forage individually and living off the most palatable herbs and the fruit which grew wild on the trees. They were driven together into societies for fear of wild animals, he said. He believed that these early people had no language, but that they gradually began to articulate their expressions, establishing symbols for every sort of object, and in this manner came to understand each other. He says that the earliest men lived laboriously, having none of the utilities of life; clothing, houses, fire, domestication, and farming were unknown to them. Democritus presents the early period of mankind as one of learning by trial and error, and says that each step slowly led to more discoveries; they took refuge in the caves in winter, stored fruits that could be preserved, and through reason and keenness of mind came to build upon each new idea. Democritus held that the Earth was round, and stated that originally the universe was composed of nothing but tiny atoms churning in chaos, until they collided together to form larger units — including the earth and everything on it. He surmised that there are many worlds, some growing, some decaying; some with no sun or moon, some with several. He held that every world has a beginning and an end, and that a world could be destroyed by collision with another world. To epitomize Democritus's cosmology, Russell calls on Shelley: "Worlds on worlds are rolling ever / From creation to decay, / Like the bubbles on a river / Sparkling, bursting, borne away." |