April 03, 2020 <Back to Index>
PAGE SPONSOR |
Plato (Greek: Πλάτων, "broad"; 424 / 423 BC – 348 / 347 BC) was a Classical Greek philosopher, mathematician, student of Socrates, writer of philosophical dialogues, and founder of the Academy in Athens, the first institution of higher learning in the Western world. Along with his mentor, Socrates, and his student, Aristotle, Plato helped to lay the foundations of Western philosophy and science. In the words of A.N. Whitehead:
Plato's sophistication as a writer is evident in his Socratic dialogs; thirty -
six dialogs and thirteen letters have been ascribed to
him. Plato's writings have been published in several
fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding
the naming and referencing of Plato's texts. Plato's
dialogs have been used to teach a range of subjects,
including philosophy, logic, ethics, rhetoric and
mathematics. The exact place and time of Plato's birth are not known, but it is certain that he belonged to an aristocratic and influential family. Based on ancient sources, most modern scholars believe that he was born in Athens or Aegina between 429 and 423 BC. His father was Ariston. According to a disputed tradition, reported by Diogenes Laertius, Ariston traced his descent from the king of Athens, Codrus, and the king of Messenia, Melanthus. Plato's mother was Perictione, whose family boasted of a relationship with the famous Athenian lawmaker and lyric poet Solon. Perictione was sister of Charmides and niece of Critias, both prominent figures of the Thirty Tyrants, the brief oligarchic regime, which followed on the collapse of Athens at the end of the Peloponnesian War (404 – 403 BC). Besides Plato himself, Ariston and Perictione had three other children; these were two sons, Adeimantus and Glaucon, and a daughter Potone, the mother of Speusippus (the nephew and successor of Plato as head of his philosophical Academy). According to the Republic, Adeimantus and Glaucon were older than Plato. Nevertheless, in his Memorabilia, Xenophon presents Glaucon as younger than Plato. The traditional date of Plato's birth (428 / 427) is based on a dubious interpretation of Diogenes Laertius, who says, "When [Socrates] was gone, [Plato] joined Cratylus the Heracleitean and Hermogenes, who philosophized in the manner of Parmenides. Then, at twenty - eight, Hermodorus says, [Plato] went to Euclides in Megara." As Debra Nails argues, "The text itself gives no reason to infer that Plato left immediately for Megara and implies the very opposite." In his Seventh Letter Plato notes that his coming of age coincided with the taking of power by the Thirty, remarking, "But a youth under the age of twenty made himself a laughingstock if he attempted to enter the political arena." Thus Nails dates Plato's birth to 424 / 423. According to some accounts, Ariston tried to force his attentions on Perictione, but failed in his purpose; then the god Apollo appeared to him in a vision, and as a result, Ariston left Perictione unmolested. Another legend related that, when Plato was an infant, bees settled on his lips while he was sleeping: an augury of the sweetness of style in which he would discourse philosophy. Ariston appears to have died in Plato's childhood, although the precise dating of his death is difficult. Perictione then married Pyrilampes, her mother's brother, who had served many times as an ambassador to the Persian court and was a friend of Pericles, the leader of the democratic faction in Athens. Pyrilampes had a son from a previous marriage, Demus, who was famous for his beauty. Perictione gave birth to Pyrilampes' second son, Antiphon, the half - brother of Plato, who appears in Parmenides. In contrast to his reticence about himself, Plato often introduced his distinguished relatives into his dialogs, or referred to them with some precision: Charmides has a dialog named after him; Critias speaks in both Charmides and Protagoras; and Adeimantus and Glaucon take prominent parts in the Republic. These and other references suggest a considerable amount of family pride and enable us to reconstruct Plato's family tree. According to Burnet, "the opening scene of the Charmides is a glorification of the whole [family] connection ... Plato's dialogs are not only a memorial to Socrates, but also the happier days of his own family."
According to Diogenes Laërtius, the philosopher was
named Aristocles after his grandfather, but his
wrestling coach, Ariston of Argos, dubbed him "Platon",
meaning "broad," on account of his robust figure.
According to the sources mentioned by Diogenes (all dating
from the Alexandrian period),
Plato derived his name from the breadth (platytęs)
of his eloquence, or else because he was very wide (platýs)
across the forehead. In the 21st century some scholars
disputed Diogenes, and argued that the legend about his
name being Aristocles originated in the
Hellenistic age. Apuleius informs us that Speusippus praised Plato's quickness of mind and modesty as a boy, and the "first fruits of his youth infused with hard work and love of study". Plato must have been instructed in grammar, music and gymnastics by the most distinguished teachers of his time. Dicaearchus went so far as to say that Plato wrestled at the Isthmian games. Plato had also attended courses of philosophy; before meeting Socrates, he first became acquainted with Cratylus (a disciple of Heraclitus, a prominent pre - Socratic Greek philosopher) and the Heraclitean doctrines. Early Hebrew language
chronology works indicate that Plato met Jeremiah in Egypt
and was thereby influenced by him. It is recorded that he
initially perceived Jeremiah to be absurd. The precise relationship between Plato and Socrates remains an area of contention among scholars. Plato makes it clear in his Apology of Socrates, that he was a devoted young follower. In that dialog, Socrates is presented as mentioning Plato by name as one of those youths close enough to him to have been corrupted, if he were in fact guilty of corrupting the youth, and questioning why their fathers and brothers did not step forward to testify against him if he was indeed guilty of such a crime (33d - 34a). Later, Plato is mentioned along with Crito, Critobolus, and Apollodorus as offering to pay a fine of 30 minas on Socrates' behalf, in lieu of the death penalty proposed by Meletus (38b). In the Phaedo, the title character lists those who were in attendance at the prison on Socrates' last day, explaining Plato's absence by saying, "Plato was ill" (Phaedo 59b). Plato never speaks in his own voice in his dialogs. In the Second Letter, it says, "no writing of Plato exists or ever will exist, but those now said to be his are those of a Socrates become beautiful and new" (341c); if the Letter is Plato's, the final qualification seems to call into question the dialogs' historical fidelity. In any case, Xenophon and Aristophanes seem to present a somewhat different portrait of Socrates than Plato paints. Some have called attention to the problem of taking Plato's Socrates to be his mouthpiece, given Socrates' reputation for irony and the dramatic nature of the dialog form. Aristotle attributes a different doctrine with respect to
the ideas to Plato and
Socrates (Metaphysics 987b1 – 11). Putting it in a
nutshell, Aristotle merely suggests that his idea of forms
can be discovered through investigation of the natural
world, unlike Plato's Forms that exist beyond and outside
the ordinary range of human understanding. Plato may have traveled in Italy, Sicily, Egypt and Cyrene. Said to have returned to Athens at the age of forty, Plato founded one of the earliest known organized schools in Western Civilization on a plot of land in the Grove of Hecademus or Academus. The Academy was "a large enclosure of ground that was once the property of a citizen at Athens named Academus (some, however, say that it received its name from an ancient hero). The Academy operated until it was destroyed by Lucius Cornelius Sulla in 84 BC. Neoplatonists revived the Academy in the early 5th century, and it operated until AD 529, when it was closed by Justinian I of Byzantium, who saw it as a threat to the propagation of Christianity. Many intellectuals were schooled in the Academy, the most prominent one being Aristotle. Throughout his later life, Plato became entangled with the politics of the city of Syracuse. According to Diogenes Laertius, Plato initially visited Syracuse while it was under the rule of Dionysus. During this first trip Dionysus's brother - in - law, Dion of Syracuse, became one of Plato's disciples, but the tyrant himself turned against Plato. Plato was sold into slavery and almost faced death in Cyrene, a city at war with Athens, before an admirer bought Plato's freedom and sent him home. After Dionysius's death, according to Plato's Seventh Letter, Dion requested Plato return to Syracuse to tutor Dionysus II and guide him to become a philosopher king. Dionysius II seemed to accept Plato's teachings, but he became suspicious of Dion, his uncle. Dionysus expelled Dion and kept Plato against his will. Eventually Plato left Syracuse. Dion would return to overthrow Dionysus and ruled Syracuse for a short time before being usurped by Calippus, a fellow disciple of Plato. A variety of sources have given accounts of Plato's
death. One story, based on a mutilated manuscript,
suggests Plato died in his bed, whilst a young Thracian girl played the
flute to him.
Another tradition suggests Plato died at a wedding feast.
The account is based on Diogenes Laertius's reference to
an account by Hermippus, a third century Alexandrian.
According to Tertullian, Plato simply died in his sleep. Plato often discusses the father - son relationship and the "question" of whether a father's interest in his sons has much to do with how well his sons turn out. A boy in ancient Athens was socially located by his family identity, and Plato often refers to his characters in terms of their paternal and fraternal relationships. Socrates was not a family man, and saw himself as the son of his mother, who was apparently a midwife. A divine fatalist, Socrates mocks men who spent exorbitant fees on tutors and trainers for their sons, and repeatedly ventures the idea that good character is a gift from the gods. Crito reminds Socrates that orphans are at the mercy of chance, but Socrates is unconcerned. In the Theaetetus, he is found recruiting as a disciple a young man whose inheritance has been squandered. Socrates twice compares the relationship of the older man and his boy lover to the father - son relationship (Lysis 213a, Republic 3.403b), and in the Phaedo, Socrates' disciples, towards whom he displays more concern than his biological sons, say they will feel "fatherless" when he is gone. In several dialogs, Socrates floats the idea that knowledge is a matter of recollection, and not of learning, observation, or study. He maintains this view somewhat at his own expense, because in many dialogs, Socrates complains of his forgetfulness. Socrates is often found arguing that knowledge is not empirical, and that it comes from divine insight. In many middle period dialogs, such as the Phaedo, Republic and Phaedrus Plato advocates a belief in the immortality of the soul, and several dialogs end with long speeches imagining the afterlife. More than one dialog contrasts knowledge and opinion, perception and reality, nature and custom, and body and soul. Several dialogs tackle questions about art: Socrates says that poetry is inspired by the muses, and is not rational. He speaks approvingly of this, and other forms of divine madness (drunkenness, eroticism and dreaming) in the Phaedrus (265a–c), and yet in the Republic wants to outlaw Homer's great poetry, and laughter as well. In Ion, Socrates gives no hint of the disapproval of Homer that he expresses in the Republic. The dialogue Ion suggests that Homer's Iliad functioned in the ancient Greek world as the Bible does today in the modern Christian world: as divinely inspired literature that can provide moral guidance, if only it can be properly interpreted. On politics and art, religion and science, justice and
medicine, virtue and vice, crime and punishment, pleasure
and pain, rhetoric and rhapsody, human nature and
sexuality, love and wisdom, Socrates and his company of
disputants had something to say. "Platonism" is a term coined by scholars to refer to the intellectual consequences of denying, as Socrates often does, the reality of the material world. In several dialogs, most notably the Republic, Socrates inverts the common man's intuition about what is knowable and what is real. While most people take the objects of their senses to be real if anything is, Socrates is contemptuous of people who think that something has to be graspable in the hands to be real. In the Theaetetus, he says such people are "eu a-mousoi", an expression that means literally, "happily without the muses" (Theaetetus 156a). In other words, such people live without the divine inspiration that gives him, and people like him, access to higher insights about reality. Socrates's idea that reality is unavailable to those who use their senses is what puts him at odds with the common man, and with common sense. Socrates says that he who sees with his eyes is blind, and this idea is most famously captured in his allegory of the cave, and more explicitly in his description of the divided line. The allegory of the cave (begins Republic 7.514a) is a paradoxical analogy wherein Socrates argues that the invisible world is the most intelligible ("noeton") and that the visible world ("(h)oraton") is the least knowable, and the most obscure. Socrates says in the Republic that people who take the sun-lit world of the senses to be good and real are living pitifully in a den of evil and ignorance. Socrates admits that few climb out of the den, or cave of ignorance, and those who do, not only have a terrible struggle to attain the heights, but when they go back down for a visit or to help other people up, they find themselves objects of scorn and ridicule. According to Socrates, physical objects and physical events are "shadows" of their ideal or perfect forms, and exist only to the extent that they instantiate the perfect versions of themselves. Just as shadows are temporary, inconsequential epiphenomena produced by physical objects, physical objects are themselves fleeting phenomena caused by more substantial causes, the ideals of which they are mere instances. For example, Socrates thinks that perfect justice exists (although it is not clear where) and his own trial would be a cheap copy of it. The allegory of the cave (often said by scholars to represent Plato's own epistemology and metaphysics) is intimately connected to his political ideology (often said to also be Plato's own), that only people who have climbed out of the cave and cast their eyes on a vision of goodness are fit to rule. Socrates claims that the enlightened men of society must be forced from their divine contemplations and be compelled to run the city according to their lofty insights. Thus is born the idea of the "philosopher - king", the wise person who accepts the power thrust upon him by the people who are wise enough to choose a good master. This is the main thesis of Socrates in the Republic, that the most wisdom the masses can muster is the wise choice of a ruler. The word metaphysics derives from the fact that Aristotle's musings about divine reality came after ("meta") his lecture notes on his treatise on nature ("physics"). The term is in fact applied to Aristotle's own teacher, and Plato's "metaphysics" is understood as Socrates' division of reality into the warring and irreconcilable domains of the material and the spiritual. The theory has been of incalculable influence in the history of Western philosophy and religion. The Theory of Forms (Greek: ἰδέαι) typically refers to the belief
expressed by Socrates in some of Plato's dialogs, that the
material world as it seems to us is not the real world,
but only an image or copy of the real world. Socrates
spoke of forms in formulating a solution to the problem of
universals. The forms, according to Socrates, are roughly
speaking archetypes or abstract representations of the
many types of things,
and properties we feel
and see around us, that can only be perceived by reason
(Greek: λογική);
(that is, they are universals). In other words, Socrates
sometimes seems to recognize two worlds: the apparent
world, which constantly changes, and an unchanging and
unseen world of forms, which may be a cause of what is
apparent. Many have interpreted Plato as stating that knowledge is justified true belief, an influential view that informed future developments in modern analytic epistemology. This interpretation is based on a reading of the Theaetetus wherein Plato argues that belief is to be distinguished from knowledge on account of justification. Many years later, Edmund Gettier famously demonstrated the problems of the justified true belief account of knowledge. This interpretation, however, imports modern analytic and empiricist categories onto Plato himself and is better read on its own terms than as Plato's view. Really, in the Sophist, Statesman, Republic, and the Parmenides Plato himself associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another (which he calls "expertise" in Dialectic). More explicitly, Plato himself argues in the Timaeus that knowledge is always proportionate to the realm from which it is gained. In other words, if one derives one's account of something experientially, because the world of sense is in flux, the views therein attained will be mere opinions. And opinions are characterized by a lack of necessity and stability. On the other hand, if one derives one's account of something by way of the non - sensible forms, because these forms are unchanging, so too is the account derived from them. It is only in this sense that Plato uses the term "knowledge". In the Meno, Socrates
uses a geometrical example to expound Plato's view that
knowledge in this latter sense is acquired by
recollection. Socrates elicits a fact concerning a
geometrical construction from a slave boy, who could not
have otherwise known the fact (due to the slave boy's lack
of education). The knowledge must be present, Socrates
concludes, in an eternal, non - experiential form. Plato's philosophical views had many societal implications, especially on the idea of an ideal state or government. There is some discrepancy between his early and later views. Some of the most famous doctrines are contained in the Republic during his middle period, as well as in the Laws and the Statesman. However, because Plato wrote dialogs, it is assumed that Socrates is often speaking for Plato. This assumption may not be true in all cases. Plato, through the words of Socrates, asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite / spirit / reason structure of the individual soul. The appetite / spirit / reason stand for different parts of the body. The body parts symbolize the castes of society.
According to this model, the principles of Athenian democracy (as it existed in his day) are rejected as only a few are fit to rule. Instead of rhetoric and persuasion, Plato says reason and wisdom should govern. As Plato puts it:
Plato describes these "philosopher kings" as "those who love the sight of truth" (Republic 475c) and supports the idea with the analogy of a captain and his ship or a doctor and his medicine. According to him, sailing and health are not things that everyone is qualified to practice by nature. A large part of the Republic then addresses how the educational system should be set up to produce these philosopher kings. However, it must be taken into account that the ideal city outlined in the Republic is qualified by Socrates as the ideal luxurious city, examined to determine how it is that injustice and justice grow in a city (Republic 372e). According to Socrates, the "true" and "healthy" city is instead the one first outlined in book II of the Republic, 369c – 372d, containing farmers, craftsmen, merchants, and wage - earners, but lacking the guardian class of philosopher - kings as well as delicacies such as "perfumed oils, incense, prostitutes and pastries", in addition to paintings, gold, ivory, couches, a multitude of occupations such as poets and hunters, and war. In addition, the ideal city is used as an image to illuminate the state of one's soul, or the will, reason, and desires combined in the human body. Socrates is attempting to make an image of a rightly ordered human, and then later goes on to describe the different kinds of humans that can be observed, from tyrants to lovers of money in various kinds of cities. The ideal city is not promoted, but only used to magnify the different kinds of individual humans and the state of their soul. However, the philosopher king image was used by many after Plato to justify their personal political beliefs. The philosophic soul according to Socrates has reason, will, and desires united in virtuous harmony. A philosopher has the moderate love for wisdom and the courage to act according to wisdom. Wisdom is knowledge about the Good or the right relations between all that exists. Wherein it concerns states and rulers, Plato has made interesting arguments. For instance he asks which is better — a bad democracy or a country reigned by a tyrant. He argues that it is better to be ruled by a bad tyrant, than be a bad democracy (since here all the people are now responsible for such actions, rather than one individual committing many bad deeds.) This is emphasized within the Republic as Plato describes the event of mutiny onboard a ship. Plato suggests the ships crew to be in line with the democratic rule of many and the captain, although inhibited through ailments, the tyrant. Plato's description of this event is parallel to that of democracy within the state and the inherent problems that arise. According to Plato, a state made up of different kinds of
souls will, overall, decline from an aristocracy (rule by
the best) to a timocracy (rule by the honorable), then to
an oligarchy (rule by the few), then to a democracy (rule
by the people), and finally to tyranny
(rule by one person, rule by a tyrant).
Aristocracy is the form of government (politeia)
advocated in Plato's Republic. This regime is ruled
by a philosopher king, and thus is grounded on wisdom and
reason. The aristocratic state, and the man whose nature
corresponds to it, are the objects of Plato's analyses
throughout much of the Republic, as opposed to the
other four types of states / men, who are discussed later
in his work. In Book VIII, Plato states in order the other
four imperfect societies with a description of the state's
structure and individual character. In timocracy the
ruling class is made up primarily of those with a warrior
like character. In his description, Plato has Sparta in
mind. Oligarchy is made up of a society in which wealth is
the criterion of merit and the wealthy are in control. In
democracy, the state bears resemblance to ancient Athens
with traits such as equality of political opportunity and
freedom for the individual to do as he likes. Democracy
then degenerates into tyranny from the conflict of rich
and poor. It is characterized by an undisciplined society
existing in chaos, where the tyrant rises as popular
champion leading to the formation of his private army and
the growth of oppression. For a long time Plato's unwritten doctrine had been controversial. Many modern books on Plato seem to diminish its importance; nevertheless the first important witness who mentions its existence is Aristotle, who in his Physics (209 b) writes: "It is true, indeed, that the account he gives there [i.e., in Timaeus] of the participant is different from what he says in his so-called unwritten teachings (ἄγραφα δόγματα)." The term ἄγραφα δόγματα literally means unwritten doctrines and it stands for the most fundamental metaphysical teaching of Plato, which he disclosed only orally, and some say only to his most trusted fellows, and which he may have kept secret from the public. The importance of the unwritten doctrines does not seem to have been seriously questioned before the 19th century. A reason for not revealing it to everyone is partially discussed in Phaedrus (276 c) where Plato criticizes the written transmission of knowledge as faulty, favoring instead the spoken logos: "he who has knowledge of the just and the good and beautiful ... will not, when in earnest, write them in ink, sowing them through a pen with words, which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth effectually." The same argument is repeated in Plato's Seventh Letter (344 c): "every serious man in dealing with really serious subjects carefully avoids writing." In the same letter he writes (341 c): "I can certainly declare concerning all these writers who claim to know the subjects that I seriously study ... there does not exist, nor will there ever exist, any treatise of mine dealing therewith." Such secrecy is necessary in order not "to expose them to unseemly and degrading treatment" (344 d). It is however said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture On the Good (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ), in which the Good (τὸ ἀγαθόν) is identified with the One (the Unity, τὸ ἕν), the fundamental ontological principle. The content of this lecture has been transmitted by several witnesses, among others Aristoxenus who describes the event in the following words: "Each came expecting to learn something about the things that are generally considered good for men, such as wealth, good health, physical strength, and altogether a kind of wonderful happiness. But when the mathematical demonstrations came, including numbers, geometrical figures and astronomy, and finally the statement Good is One seemed to them, I imagine, utterly unexpected and strange; hence some belittled the matter, while others rejected it." Simplicius quotes Alexander of Aphrodisias who states that "according to Plato, the first principles of everything, including the Forms themselves are One and Indefinite Duality (ἡ ἀόριστος δυάς), which he called Large and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν) ... one might also learn this from Speusippus and Xenocrates and the others who were present at Plato's lecture on the Good" Their account is in full agreement with Aristotle's description of Plato's metaphysical doctrine. In Metaphysics he writes: "Now since the Forms are the causes of everything else, he [i.e., Plato] supposed that their elements are the elements of all things. Accordingly the material principle is the Great and Small [i.e., the Dyad], and the essence is the One (τὸ ἕν), since the numbers are derived from the Great and Small by participation in the One" (987 b). "From this account it is clear that he only employed two causes: that of the essence, and the material cause; for the Forms are the cause of the essence in everything else, and the One is the cause of it in the Forms. He also tells us what the material substrate is of which the Forms are predicated in the case of sensible things, and the One in that of the Forms - that it is this the duality (the Dyad, ἡ δυάς), the Great and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν). Further, he assigned to these two elements respectively the causation of good and of evil" (988 a). The most important aspect of this interpretation of Plato's metaphysics is the continuity between his teaching and the neoplatonic interpretation of Plotinus or Ficino which has been considered erroneous by many but may in fact have been directly influenced by oral transmission of Plato's doctrine. A modern scholar who recognized the importance of the unwritten doctrine of Plato was Heinrich Gomperz who described it in his speech during the 7th International Congress of Philosophy in 1930. All the sources related to the ἄγραφα δόγματα have been collected by Konrad Gaiser and published as Testimonia Platonica. These sources have subsequently been interpreted by scholars from the German Tübingen School such as Hans Joachim Krämer or Thomas A. Szlezák. The
role of dialectic in Plato's thought is contested but
there are two main interpretations; a type of reasoning
and a method of intuition. Simon Blackburn
adopts the first, saying that Plato's dialectic is “the
process of eliciting the truth by means of questions aimed
at opening out what is already implicitly known, or at
exposing the contradictions and muddles of an opponent’s
position.”
Karl Popper, on the other hand, claims that dialectic is
the art of intuition for "visualizing the divine
originals, the Forms or Ideas, of unveiling the Great
Mystery behind the common man's everyday world of
appearances." Thirty - six dialogs and thirteen letters have traditionally been ascribed to Plato, though modern scholarship doubts the authenticity of at least some of these. Plato's writings have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts. The usual system for making unique references to sections of the text by Plato derives from a 16th century edition of Plato's works by Henricus Stephanus. An overview of Plato's writings according to this system can be found in the Stephanus pagination article. One tradition regarding the arrangement of Plato's texts
is according to tetralogies. This scheme is ascribed by
Diogenes Laertius to an ancient scholar and court
astrologer to Tiberius named Thrasyllus. No one knows the exact order Plato's dialogs were written in, nor the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten. Lewis Campbell was the first to make exhaustive use of stylometry to prove objectively that the Critias, Timaeus, Laws, Philebus, Sophist and Statesman were all clustered together as a group, while the Parmenides, Phaedrus, Republic and Theaetetus belong to a separate group, which must be earlier (given Aristotle's statement in his Politics that the Laws was written after the Republic; cf. Diogenes Laertius Lives 3.37). What is remarkable about Campbell's conclusions is that, in spite of all the stylometric studies that have been conducted since his time, perhaps the only chronological fact about Plato's works that can now be said to be proven by stylometry is the fact that Critias, Timaeus, Laws, Philebus, Sophist and Statesman are the latest of Plato's dialogs, the others earlier. Increasingly in the most recent Plato scholarship, writers are skeptical of the notion that the order of Plato's writings can be established with any precision, though Plato's works are still often characterized as falling at least roughly into three groups. The following represents one relatively common such division. It should, however, be kept in mind that many of the positions in the ordering are still highly disputed, and also that the very notion that Plato's dialogs can or should be "ordered" is by no means universally accepted. Among those who classify the dialogs into periods of composition, Socrates figures in all of the "early dialogs" and they are considered the most faithful representations of the historical Socrates. They include The Apology of Socrates, Charmides, Crito, Euthyphro, Ion, Laches, Less Hippias, Lysis, Menexenus and Protagoras (often considered one of the last of the "early dialogs"). Three dialogs are often considered "transitional" or "pre-middle": Euthydemus, Gorgias and Meno. Whereas those classified as "early dialogs" often conclude in aporia, the so-called "middle dialogs" provide more clearly stated positive teachings that are often ascribed to Plato such as the theory of forms. These dialogs include Cratylus, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Republic, Symposium, Parmenides and Theaetetus. Proponents of dividing the dialogues into periods often consider the Parmenides and Theaetetus to come late in this period and be transitional to the next, as they seem to treat the theory of forms critically (Parmenides) or not at all (Theaetetus). The remaining dialogues are classified as "late" and are generally agreed to be difficult and challenging pieces of philosophy. This grouping is the only one proven by stylometric analysis. While looked to for Plato's "mature" answers to the questions posed by his earlier works, those answers are difficult to discern. Some scholars say that the theory of forms is absent from the late dialogues, its having been refuted in the Parmenides, but there isn't total consensus that the Parmenides actually refutes the theory of forms. The so-called "late dialogs" include Critias, Laws, Philebus, Sophist, Statesman and Timaeus.
Plato never presents himself as a participant in any
of the dialogs, and with the exception of the Apology,
there is no suggestion that he heard any of the dialogs
firsthand. Some dialogs have no narrator but have a pure
"dramatic" form (examples: Meno, Gorgias, Phaedrus, Crito,
Euthyphro), some dialogs are narrated by Socrates,
wherein he speaks in first person (examples: Lysis,
Charmides, Republic).
One dialog, Protagoras, begins in dramatic form
but quickly proceeds to Socrates' narration of a
conversation he had previously with the sophist for whom
the dialog is named; this narration continues
uninterrupted till the dialog's end. Two dialogs Phaedo and Symposium also begin in dramatic form but then proceed to virtually uninterrupted narration by followers of Socrates. Phaedo, an account of Socrates' final conversation and hemlock drinking, is narrated by Phaedo to Echecrates in a foreign city not long after the execution took place. The Symposium is narrated by Apollodorus, a Socratic disciple, apparently to Glaucon. Apollodorus assures his listener that he is recounting the story, which took place when he himself was an infant, not from his own memory, but as remembered by Aristodemus, who told him the story years ago. The Theaetetus is a peculiar case: a dialog in
dramatic form imbedded within another dialog in dramatic
form. In the beginning of the Theaetetus (142c -
143b), Euclides says that he compiled the conversation
from notes he took based on what Socrates told him of his
conversation with the title character. The rest of the Theaetetus
is presented as a "book" written in dramatic form and read
by one of Euclides' slaves (143c). Some scholars take this
as an indication that Plato had by this date wearied of
the narrated form.
With the exception of the Theaetetus, Plato gives
no explicit indication as to how these orally transmitted
conversations came to be written down. The trial of Socrates is the central, unifying event of the great Platonic dialogs. Because of this, Plato's Apology is perhaps the most often read of the dialogs. In the Apology, Socrates tries to dismiss rumors that he is a sophist and defends himself against charges of disbelief in the gods and corruption of the young. Socrates insists that long standing slander will be the real cause of his demise, and says the legal charges are essentially false. Socrates famously denies being wise, and explains how his life as a philosopher was launched by the Oracle at Delphi. He says that his quest to resolve the riddle of the oracle put him at odds with his fellow man, and that this is the reason he has been mistaken for a menace to the city - state of Athens. If Plato's important dialogs do not refer to Socrates'
execution explicitly, they allude to it, or use characters
or themes that play a part in it. Five dialogs foreshadow
the trial: In the Theaetetus (210d) and the Euthyphro
(2a–b) Socrates tells people that he is about to face
corruption charges. In the Meno (94e – 95a), one
of the men who brings legal charges against Socrates,
Anytus, warns him about the trouble he may get into if he
does not stop criticizing important people. In the Gorgias,
Socrates says that his trial will be like a doctor
prosecuted by a cook who asks a jury of children to choose
between the doctor's bitter medicine and the cook's tasty
treats (521e – 522a). In the Republic (7.517e),
Socrates explains why an enlightened man (presumably
himself) will stumble in a courtroom situation. The Apology
is Socrates' defense speech, and the Crito and Phaedo
take place in prison after the conviction. In the Protagoras,
Socrates is a guest at the home of Callias, son of Hipponicus, a man whom
Socrates disparages in the Apology as having
wasted a great amount of money on sophists' fees. Two other important dialogues, the Symposium and the Phaedrus, are linked to the main storyline by characters. In the Apology (19b, c), Socrates says Aristophanes slandered him in a comic play, and blames him for causing his bad reputation, and ultimately, his death. In the Symposium, the two of them are drinking together with other friends. The character Phaedrus is linked to the main story line by character (Phaedrus is also a participant in the Symposium and the Protagoras) and by theme (the philosopher as divine emissary, etc.) The Protagoras is also strongly linked to the Symposium by characters: all of the formal speakers at the Symposium (with the exception of Aristophanes) are present at the home of Callias in that dialog. Charmides and his guardian Critias are present for the discussion in the Protagoras. Examples of characters crossing between dialogs can be further multiplied. The Protagoras contains the largest gathering of Socratic associates. In the dialogs Plato is most celebrated and admired for,
Socrates is concerned with human and political virtue, has
a distinctive personality, and friends and enemies who
"travel" with him from dialog to dialog. This is not to
say that Socrates is consistent: a man who is his friend
in one dialog may be an adversary or subject of his
mockery in another. For example, Socrates praises the
wisdom of Euthyphro many times in the Cratylus,
but makes him look like a fool in the Euthyphro.
He disparages sophists generally, and Prodicus
specifically in the Apology, whom he also slyly
jabs in the Cratylus for charging the hefty fee of
fifty drachmas for a
course on language and grammar. However, Socrates tells
Theaetetus in his namesake dialog that he admires Prodicus
and has directed many pupils to him. Socrates' ideas are
also not consistent within or between or among dialogs. Although their popularity has fluctuated over the years, the works of Plato have never been without readers since the time they were written. Plato's thought is often compared with that of his most famous student, Aristotle, whose reputation during the Western Middle Ages so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the Scholastic philosophers referred to Aristotle as "the Philosopher". However, in the Byzantine Empire, the study of Plato continued. The Medieval scholastic philosophers did not have access to the works of Plato, nor the knowledge of Greek needed to read them. Plato's original writings were essentially lost to Western civilization until they were brought from Constantinople in the century of its fall, by George Gemistos Plethon. It is believed that Plethon passed a copy of the Dialogs to Cosimo de' Medici when in 1438 the Council of Ferrara, called to unify the Greek and Latin Churches, was adjourned to Florence, where Plethon then lectured on the relation and differences of Plato and Aristotle, and fired Cosimo with his enthusiasm. Medieval scholars knew of Plato only through translations into Latin from the translations into Arabic by Persian and Arab scholars. These scholars not only translated the texts of the ancients, but expanded them by writing extensive commentaries and interpretations on Plato's and Aristotle's works (see Al-Farabi, Avicenna, Averroes). Only in the Renaissance, with the general resurgence of interest in classical civilization, did knowledge of Plato's philosophy become widespread again in the West. Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with Scholasticism and fostered the flowering of the Renaissance, with the support of the Plato - inspired Lorenzo de Medici, saw Plato's philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences. By the 19th century, Plato's reputation was restored, and at least on par with Aristotle's. Notable Western philosophers have continued to draw upon
Plato's work since that time. Plato's influence has been
especially strong in mathematics and the sciences. He
helped to distinguish between pure and applied mathematics
by widening the gap between "arithmetic", now called
number theory and "logistic", now called arithmetic. He
regarded logistic as appropriate for business men and men
of war who "must learn the art of numbers or he will not
know how to array his troops," while arithmetic was
appropriate for philosophers "because he has to arise out
of the sea of change and lay hold of true being."
Plato's resurgence further inspired some of the greatest
advances in logic since Aristotle, primarily through
Gottlob Frege and his followers Kurt Gödel, Alonzo Church
and Alfred Tarski; the last of these summarized his
approach by reversing the customary paraphrase of
Aristotle's famous declaration of sedition from the
Academy (Nicomachean Ethics 1096a15), from Amicus
Plato sed magis amica veritas ("Plato is a friend,
but truth is a greater friend") to Inimicus Plato sed
magis inimica falsitas ("Plato is an enemy, but
falsehood is a greater enemy"). Albert Einstein drew on
Plato's understanding of an immutable reality that
underlies the flux of appearances for his objections to
the probabilistic picture of the physical universe
propounded by Niels Bohr in his interpretation of quantum
mechanics. Conversely, thinkers that diverged from
ontological models and moral ideals in their own
philosophy, have tended to disparage Platonism from more
or less informed perspectives. Thus Friedrich Nietzsche
attacked Plato's moral and political theories, Martin
Heidegger argued against Plato's alleged obfuscation of Being,
and Karl Popper argued in The Open Society and Its
Enemies (1945) that Plato's alleged proposal for a
government system in the Republic was
prototypically totalitarian. Leo Strauss is considered by
some as the prime thinker involved in the recovery of
Platonic thought in its more political, and less
metaphysical, form. Deeply influenced by Nietzsche and
Heidegger, Strauss nonetheless rejects their condemnation
of Plato and looks to the dialogs for a solution to what
all three thinkers acknowledge as 'the crisis of the
West.' The texts of Plato as received today apparently represent the complete written philosophical work of Plato and are generally good by the standards of textual criticism. No modern edition of Plato in the original Greek represents a single source, but rather it is reconstructed from multiple sources which are compared with each other. These sources are medieval manuscripts written on vellum (mainly from 9th - 13th century AD Byzantium), papyri (mainly from late antiquity in Egypt), and from the independent testimonia of other authors who quote various segments of the works (which come from a variety of sources). The text as presented is usually not much different than what appears in the Byzantine manuscripts, and papyri and testimonia just confirm the manuscript tradition. In some editions however the readings in the papyri or testimonia are favored in some places by the editing critic of the text. In the first century AD, Thrasyllus of Mendes had compiled and published the works of Plato in the original Greek, both genuine and spurious. While it has not survived to the present day, all the extant medieval Greek manuscripts are based on his edition. The oldest surviving complete manuscript for many of the dialogs is the Clarke Plato (Codex Oxoniensis Clarkianus 39, or Codex Boleianus MS E.D. Clarke 39), which was written in Constantinople in 895 and acquired by Oxford University in 1809. The Clarke is given the siglum B in modern editions. B contains the first six tetralogies and is described internally as being written by "John the Calligrapher" on behalf of Arethas of Caesarea. It appears to have undergone corrections by Arethas himself. For the last two tetralogies and the apocrypha, the oldest surviving complete manuscript is Codex Parisinus graecus 1807, designated A, which was written nearly contemporaneously to B, circa 900 AD. A probably had an initial volume containing the first 7 tetralogies which is now lost, but of which a copy was made, Codex Venetus append. class. 4, 1, which has the siglum T. The oldest manuscript for the seventh tetralogy is Codex Vindobonensis 54. suppl. phil. Gr. 7, with siglum W, with a supposed date in the twelfth century. In total there are fifty - one such Byzantine manuscripts known, while others may yet be found. To help establish the text, the older evidence of papyri and the independent evidence of the testimony of commentators and other authors (i.e., those who quote and refer to an old text of Plato which is so longer extant) are also used. Many papyri which contain fragments of Plato's texts are among the Oxyrhynchus Papyri. The 2003 Oxford Classical Texts edition by Slings even cites the Coptic translation of a fragment of the Republic in the Nag Hammadi library as evidence. Important authors for testimony include Olympiodorus the Younger, Plutarch, Proclus, Iamblichus, Eusebius and Stobaeus. During the early Renaissance, the Greek language and,
along with it, Plato's texts were reintroduced to Western
Europe by Byzantine scholars. In 1483 there was published
a Latin edition of Plato's complete works translated by
Marsilio Ficino at the behest of Cosimo de' Medici.
Cosimo had been influenced toward studying Plato by the
many Byzantine Platonists in Florence during his day,
including George Gemistus
Plethon. Henri Estienne's edition, including
parallel Greek and Latin, was published in 1578. It was
this edition which established Stephanus pagination, still
in use today. The Oxford Classical Texts offers the current standard complete Greek text of Plato's complete works. In five volumes edited by John Burnet, its first edition was published 1900 - 1907, and it is still available from the publisher, having last been printed in 1993. The second edition is still in progress with only the first volume, printed in 1995, and the Republic, printed in 2003, available. The Cambridge Greek and Latin Texts and Cambridge Classical Texts and Commentaries series includes Greek editions of the Protagoras, Symposium, Phaedrus, Alcibiades, and Clitophon, with English philological, literary, and, to an extent, philosophical commentary. One distinguished edition of the Greek text is E. R. Dodds' of the Gorgias, which includes extensive English commentary. The modern standard complete English edition is the 1997
Hackett Plato, Complete Works, edited by John M.
Cooper.
For many of these translations Hackett offers separate
volumes which include more by way of commentary, notes,
and introductory material. There is also the
Clarendon Plato Series by Oxford University Press
which offers English translations and thorough
philosophical commentary by leading scholars on a few of
Plato's works, including John McDowell's version of the
Theaetetus.
Cornell University Press has also begun the Agora
series of English translations of classical and medieval
philosophical texts, including a few of Plato's. Carl Sagan said of Plato: "Science and mathematics were to be removed from the hands of the merchants and the artisans. This tendency found its most effective advocate in a follower of Pythagoras named Plato." and: "He (Plato) believed that ideas were far more real than the natural world. He advised the astronomers not to waste their time observing the stars and planets. It was better, he believed, just to think about them. Plato expressed hostility to observation and experiment. He taught contempt for the real world and disdain for the practical application of scientific knowledge. Plato's followers succeeded in extinguishing the light of science and experiment that had been kindled by Democritus and the other Ionians." |